-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 1
/
Copy pathblack5_2010.tex
2873 lines (2575 loc) · 153 KB
/
black5_2010.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
\input grafinp3
%\input grafinput8
\input psfig
\def\th{{\theta}}
%\eqnotracetrue
%\showchaptIDtrue
%\def\@chaptID{5.}
%\input gayejnl.txt
%\input gayedef.txt
\def\lege{\raise.3ex\hbox{$>$\kern-.75em\lower1ex\hbox{$<$}}}
\def\be{{\beta}}
%\hbox{}
\chapter{Search and Unemployment\label{search1}}
\footnum=0
\section{Introduction}
This chapter applies dynamic programming to a choice between
two actions, to accept or reject a take-it-or-leave-it
job offer. An unemployed worker faces a probability distribution
of wage offers or job characteristics from which a limited
number of offers are drawn each period. Given his perception
of the probability distribution of offers, the worker must
devise a strategy for deciding when to accept an offer.
\auth{McCall, John} \auth{Jovanovic, Boyan} \auth{Stigler, George} \auth{Neal, Derek} %
The theory of search is a tool for studying unemployment.
Search theory puts unemployed workers in a setting where
they sometimes choose to reject available offers and to remain
unemployed now because they prefer to wait for better offers later.
We use the theory to study how workers respond
to variations in the rate of unemployment compensation,
the perceived riskiness of wage distributions, the probability of
being fired, the quality of
information about jobs, and the frequency with which a wage
distribution can be sampled.
This chapter provides an introduction to the techniques used in
the search literature and a sampling of search models. The chapter
studies ideas introduced in two important papers by McCall
(1970) and Jovanovic (1979a). These papers differ in the search technologies
with which they confront an unemployed worker.\NFootnote{Stigler's (1961)
important early paper studied a search technology different
from both McCall's and Jovanovic's. In Stigler's model,
an unemployed worker has to choose in advance a number $n$
of offers to draw, from which he takes the highest wage offer.
Stigler's formulation of the search problem was not sequential.}
We also study a related model of occupational choice by Neal (1999).
We hope to convey some of the excitement that Robert E. Lucas, Jr. (1987, p.57)
expressed when he wrote this about the McCall search model:
``Questioning a McCall worker is like having a conversation with an out-of-work friend:
`Maybe you are setting your sights too high' or `Why did you quit your old job before
you had a new one lined up?' This is real social science: an attempt to model,
to {\it understand\/}, human behavior by visualizing the situations people find themselves in,
the options they face and the pros and cons as they themselves see them.'' The modifications
of the basic McCall model by Jovanovic, Neal, and in the various sections and exercises of this chapter all
come from visualizing aspects of the situations in which workers find themselves.
\section{Preliminaries}
This section describes elementary properties of probability distributions
that are used extensively in search theory.
\subsection{Nonnegative random variables}
We begin with some properties of nonnegative random variables that
possess finite first moments. Consider a random variable $p$ with a cumulative
probability distribution function $F(P)$ defined by ${\rm Prob}\{p\le P\} =F(P)$. We
assume that $F(0)=0$, that is, that $p$ is nonnegative. We assume
that % $F(\infty)=1$ and that
$F$, a nondecreasing function, is
continuous from the right. We also assume that there is an
upper bound $B<\infty$ such that $F(B)=1$, so that $p$ is bounded with
probability 1.
The mean of $p$, $Ep$, is defined by
$$Ep=\int_0^B p\ dF(p).\EQN 2.1$$
Let $u=1-F(p)$ and $v=p$ and use the integration-by-parts formula
$\int_a^b u\ dv=uv \Big\vert_a^b -\int_a^b v\ du,$
to verify that
$$\int_0^B [1-F(p)]dp =\int_0^B p\ dF(p).$$
Thus, we have the following formula for the mean of a
nonnegative random variable:
$$Ep=\int_0^B [1-F(p)]dp = B - \int_0^B F(p)dp .\EQN 2.2$$
Now consider two independent random variables $p_1$ and $p_2$ drawn from the
distribution $F$. Consider the event $\{(p_1<p)\cap (p_2<p)\}$, which by the
independence assumption has probability $F(p)^2$. The event $\{(p_1<p)\cap
(p_2<p)\}$ is equivalent to the event $\{\max(p_1,p_2)<p\}$, where ``max''
denotes the maximum. Therefore, if we use formula \Ep{2.2}, the random
variable
$\max (p_1,p_2)$ has mean
$$E\max (p_1,p_2) = B - \int_0^B F(p)^2 dp %%%\equiv \int_0^B F^2(d \,p)
.\EQN 2.3$$
Similarly, if $p_1,p_2,\ldots, p_n$ are $n$ independent random variables drawn
from $F$, we have Prob$\{\max(p_1,p_2,\ldots, p_n)<p\}=F(p)^n$ and
$$M_n\equiv E\max (p_1,p_2,\ldots, p_n) = B - \int_0^B F(p)^n
dp,\EQN 2.4$$
where $M_n$ is defined as the expected value of the maximum of
$p_1,\ldots,p_n$.
\subsection{Mean-preserving spreads}
Rothschild and Stiglitz introduced the idea of a mean-preserving spread
as a convenient way to characterize the riskiness of two distributions with
the same mean. Consider a class of distributions with the same mean. We index
this class by a parameter $r$ belonging to some set $R$. For the $r$th
distribution we denote Prob$\{p\le P\} =F(P,r)$ and assume that
$F(P,r)$ is differentiable with respect to $r$ for all $P \in [0,B]$.
We assume that there is a
single finite $B$ such that $F(B,r)=1$ for all $r$ in $R$ and that $F(0,r)=0$ for all $r$ in $R$, so that we are considering
a class of distributions $R$ for nonnegative, bounded random variables.
From equation \Ep{2.2}, we have %%%$Ep=\int_0^B [1-F(s,r)]ds$, or
$$Ep=B-\int_0^B F(p,r) dp.\EQN 2.13$$
Therefore, two distributions with the same value
of $\int_0^B F(\theta,r)d \theta$ have
identical means. We write this as the identical means condition:
$$\int_0^B [F(\th,r_1)-F(\th,r_2)]d\th=0.\leqno {\rm (i)}$$
Two distributions $r_1,r_2$ are said to satisfy the
\index{single-crossing property}%
{\it single-crossing property\/} if there exists a $\hat \th$ with
$0<\hat \th<B$ such that
$$F(\th,r_2)-F(\th,r_1) \le 0 (\ge 0)\qquad {\rm when}\quad \th\ge
(\le)\hat \th. \leqno{\rm (ii)} $$
%%%%
%\topinsert{
%$$
%\grafone{powdmt3.eps,height=2.5in,angle=-90}{{\bf Figure 5.1} Two
%distributions, $r_1$ and $r_2$, that satisfy the single-crossing
%property.}
%$$
%}\endinsert
%%%%%
\midfigure{powdmt3f}
\centerline{\epsfxsize=3truein\epsffile{powdmt3new.eps}}
\caption{Two distributions, $r_1$ and $r_2$, that satisfy the single-crossing property.}
\infiglist{powdmt3f}
\endfigure
Figure \Fg{powdmt3f} %Figure 5.1
illustrates the single-crossing property. If two distributions
$r_1$ and $r_2$ satisfy properties
(i) and (ii), we can regard distribution $r_2$ as having been obtained from
$r_1$ by a process that shifts probability toward the tails of the distribution
while keeping the mean constant.
Properties (i) and (ii) imply the following property:
$$\int_0^y [F(\th,r_2)-F(\th,r_1)] d\th \ge 0,\qquad 0\le y\le B\, .
\leqno {\rm (iii)}$$
\index{mean-preserving spread}%
Rothschild and Stiglitz regard properties (i) and (iii) as defining the concept
of a ``mean-preserving spread.'' In particular, a distribution
indexed by $r_2$ is said to have been obtained from a distribution indexed by
$r_1$ by a mean-preserving spread if the two distributions satisfy
(i) and (iii).\NFootnote{Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970, 1971) use properties
(i) and %
(iii) to characterize mean-preserving spreads rather than (i) and (ii) %
because %
(i) and (ii) fail to possess transitivity. That is, if $F(\th, r_2)$ is %
obtained from $F(\th,r_1)$ via a mean-preserving spread in the sense that the %
term has in (i) and (ii), and $F(\th,r_3)$ is obtained from $F(\th,r_2)$ via %
a %
mean-preserving spread in the sense of (i) and (ii), it does not follow that %
$F(\th,r_3)$ satisfies the single-crossing property (ii) vis-\`a-vis distribution %
$F(\th,r_1)$. A definition based on (i) and (iii), however, does provide a %
transitive ordering, which is a desirable feature for a definition designed %
to %
order distributions according to their riskiness.}
\index{single-crossing property}
For infinitesimal changes in $r$, Diamond and Stiglitz use the differential
versions of properties
(i) and (iii) to rank distributions with the same mean in order of
riskiness. An increment in $r$ is said to represent a mean-preserving increase
in risk if
$$\int_0^B F_r(\th,r)d\th=0 \leqno {\rm (iv)}$$
$$\int_0^y F_r(\th,r)d\th\ge 0,\qquad 0\le y\le B\ ,\leqno {\rm (v)}$$
where $F_r(\th,r)=\part F(\th,r)/\part r$.
\section{McCall's model of intertemporal job search}
We now consider an unemployed worker who is searching for a job
under the following circumstances: Each period the worker draws one offer $w$
from the same wage distribution $F(W)={\rm Prob}\{w\le W\}$, with $F(0)=0$,
$F(B)=1$ for $B<\infty$. The worker has the option of rejecting the offer, in
which case he or she receives $c$ this period in unemployment compensation and
waits until next period to draw another offer from $F$; alternatively, the
worker can accept the offer to work at $w$, in which case he or she receives a
wage of $w$ per period forever. Neither quitting nor firing is permitted.
Let $y_t$ be the worker's income in period $t$. We have $y_t=c$ if the
worker is unemployed and $y_t=w$ if the worker has accepted an offer to
work at wage $w$. The unemployed worker devises a strategy to maximize the mathematical expectation of
$\sum_{t=0}^\infty \be^t y_t$ where $0<\be<1$ is a discount factor.
Let $v(w)$ be the expected value of $\sum_{t=0}^\infty \be^t y_t$ for a previously unemployed worker
who has offer $w$ in hand, who is deciding whether to accept or to reject it,
and who behaves optimally. We assume no recall. The value function
$v(w)$ satisfies the Bellman
equation
$$v(w)=\max_{\rm accept, reject} \left\{ {w\over 1-\be}, c+\be\int_0^B v(w')
dF(w')\right\},\EQN 2.14$$
where the maximization is over the values of outcomes associated with the two actions: (1) {\it accept}
the wage offer $w$
and work forever at wage $w$,
or (2) {\it reject} the offer, receive $c$ this period,
and draw a new offer $w'$ from distribution $F$ next period. The value of accepting the offer is $ {w\over 1-\be}$, the present value
of the constant wage. The value of rejecting the offer is the unemployment compensation $c$ received today plus the discounted expected value
$\be\int_0^B v(w')$ of drawing a new offer and deciding optimally tomorrow.
Figure \Fg{powdmt4f} % Figure 5.2
graphs
the functional equation \Ep{2.14} and reveals that its solution is of the
form
$$\def\pear{{\eqalign{{\overline w\over 1-\be} =c+\be \int_0^B v(w')dF(w')
&\qquad{\rm if}\quad w\le\overline w\cr
{w\over 1-\be}{\hskip 4cm} & \qquad{\rm if}\quad w\ge \overline w.\cr}}}
v(w)= \left\{ \pear\right. \EQN 2.15$$
%%%%%%
%\topinsert{
%$$
%\grafone{powdmt4.eps,height=2.5in,angle=-90}{{\bf Figure 5.2}
%The function $v(w)=\max\{w/(1-\be),c+\be \int_0^B v(w')dF(w')\}$.
%The reservation wage $\overline w=(1-\be)[c+\be\int_0^B v(w')dF(w')]$.}
%$$
%}\endinsert
%%%%%
\midfigure{powdmt4f}
\centerline{\epsfxsize=3true in\epsffile{powdmt4new.eps}}
\caption{The function $v(w)=\max\{w/(1-\be),c+\be \int_0^B v(w')dF(w')\}$.
The reservation wage $\overline w=(1-\beta)[c+\be\int_0^B v(w')dF(w')]$.}
\infiglist{powdmt4f}
\endfigure
%\topfigure{r2red1a}
%\centerline{\epsfxsize=3true in\epsffile{r2red1a.eps}}
%\caption{Impulse response, spectrum, covariogram, and
%sample path
%of process $(1 - .9L) y_t = w_t $.}
%\infiglist{First order a.r.}
%\endfigure
\medskip
\noindent
Using equation \Ep{2.15}, we can convert the functional equation
\Ep{2.14} in the value function $v(w)$ into an ordinary equation in the reservation wage $\overline w$.
Evaluating $v(\overline w)$ and using equation \Ep{2.15}, we have
$$\eqalignno{ {\overline w\over 1-\be} &= c+\be \int_0^{\overline w} {\overline w\over 1-\be}
dF(w') +\be \int_{\overline w}^B {w'\over 1-\be} dF(w') \cr
\noalign{\hbox{or}}
{\overline w\over 1-\be}& \int_0^{\overline w} dF(w') +{\overline w\over 1-\be} \int_{\overline
w}^B dF (w')\cr
&= c+\be \int_0^{\overline w} {\overline w\over 1-\be} dF(w') +\be \int_{\overline w}^B
{w'\over 1-\be} dF(w')\cr
\noalign{\hbox{or}}
\overline w&\int_0^{\overline w} dF(w') -c = {1\over 1-\be} \int_{\overline w}^B (\be
w'-\overline w) dF(w').\cr}$$
Adding $\overline w\int_{\overline w}^B dF(w')$ to both sides gives
$$(\overline w-c) ={\be\over 1-\be} \int_{\overline w}^B (w'-\overline w)
dF(w').\EQN 2.16$$
Equation \Ep{2.16} is often used to characterize the
reservation wage $\overline w$. The left side is the cost of searching one more
time when an offer $\overline w$ is in hand. The right side is the expected benefit
of searching one more time in terms of the expected present value associated
with drawing $w'>\overline w$. Equation \Ep{2.16} instructs the agent to set $\overline w$
so that the cost of searching one more time equals the benefit.
\subsection{Characterizing reservation wage}
Let us define the function on the right side of equation \Ep{2.16} as
$$h(w)={\be\over 1-\be} \int_w^B (w'-w) dF(w').\EQN 2.17$$
Notice that $h(0)= Ew \be /(1-\be)$, that $h(B)=0$, and that $h(w)$ is
differentiable, with derivative given
by\NFootnote{To compute $h'(w)$, we apply Leibniz's rule to equation
\Ep{2.17}. Let
$\phi(t) = \int_{\alpha(t)}^{\beta(t)} f(x,t) d \, x $ for
$t \in[c,d]$. Assume that $f $ and $f_t$ are continuous and that $\alpha,
\beta$ are differentiable on $[c,d]$. Then Leibniz's rule asserts that
$\phi(t)$ is differentiable on $[c,d]$ and
$$ \phi'(t) = f[\beta(t),t] \beta'(t) - f[\alpha(t),t] \alpha'(t)
+ \int_{\alpha(t)}^{\beta(t)} f_t(x,t) d \, x.$$
To apply this formula
to the equation in the text, let $w$ play the role
of $t$.}
$$h'(w) =-{\be\over 1-\be} [1-F(w)]<0.$$
We also have
$$h^\pp (w) ={\be\over 1-\be} F'(w)>0,$$
so that $h(w) $ is convex to the origin. Figure \Fg{powdmt5f} %Figure 5.3
graphs $h(w)$ against
$(w-c)$ and indicates how $\overline w$ is determined. From Figure \Fg{powdmt5f} it is
apparent that an increase in unemployment compensation $c$ leads to an increase in $\overline w$.
%%%%%%
%$$
%\grafone{%powdmt5.eps,%
%fig053.ps,height=2.5in}{{\bf Figure 5.3}
% The reservation wage, $\overline w$, that satisfies $\overline
%w-c=[\be/(1-\be)]\int_{\overline w}^B (w'-\overline w) dF(w')\equiv h(\overline w)$.}
%$$
%%%%%
\midfigure{powdmt5f}
\centerline{\epsfxsize=3truein\epsffile{powdmt5.eps}}
\caption{The reservation wage $\overline w$ that satisfies $\overline
w-c=[\be/(1-\be)]\int_{\overline w}^B (w'-\overline w) dF(w')\equiv h(\overline w)$.}
\infiglist{powdmt5f}
\endfigure
To get another useful characterization of $\overline w$,
we express equation \Ep{2.16} as
$$\eqalign{ \overline w-c =& {\be\over 1-\be} \int_{\overline w}^B (w'-\overline w)
dF(w') +{\be\over 1-\be} \int_0^{\overline w} (w'-\overline w) dF(w')\cr
&- {\be\over 1-\be} \int_0^{\overline w} (w'-\overline w) dF(w')\cr
=& {\be\over 1-\be} Ew-{\be\over 1-\be} \overline w-{\be\over 1-\be} \int_0^{\overline w}
(w'-\overline w) dF(w')\cr}$$
or
$$\overline w-(1-\be)c=\be Ew-\be \int_0^{\overline w} (w'-\overline w) dF(w').$$
Applying integration by parts to the last integral on the right side and
rearranging, we have
$$\overline w-c =\be (Ew-c) +\be \int_0^{\overline w} F(w') dw'.\EQN 2.18$$
At this point it is useful to
define the function
$$g(s)=\int_0^s F(p)dp.\EQN 2.10$$
This function has the characteristics that $g(0)=0$, $g(s)\ge 0$,
$g'(s)=F(s)>0$, and $g^\pp(s)=F'(s)>0$ for $s>0$.
Then equation \Ep{2.18} can be represented as $\overline w-c=\be (Ew-c)+ \be
g(\overline w)$. %, where $g(s)$ is the function defined by equation \Ep{2.10}.
% Recall that $g'(s)
%=F(s)$, which is between zero and one, and that $g^\pp(s) =F'(s)>0$.
Figure
\Fg{powdmt6f} uses equation \Ep{2.18} to determine $\overline w$.
%%%%%%
%\topinsert{
%$$
%\grafone{powdmt6.eps,height=2.5in}{{\bf Figure 5.4}
% The reservation wage, $\overline w$, that satisfies $\overline w-c=\be
%(Ew-c)+\be \int_0^{\overline w} F(w') dw'\equiv \be (Ew-c)+\be g(\overline w)$.}
%$$
%}\endinsert
%%%%%%%
\midfigure{powdmt6f}
\centerline{\epsfxsize=3truein\epsffile{powdmt6.eps}}
\caption{The reservation wage, $\overline w$, that satisfies $\overline w-c=\be
(Ew-c)+\be \int_0^{\overline w} F(w') dw'\equiv \be (Ew-c)+\be g(\overline w)$.}
\infiglist{powdmt6f}
\endfigure
\subsection{Effects of mean-preserving spreads}
Figure \Fg{powdmt6f} %Figure 5.4
can be used to establish two propositions about
$\overline w$. First, given $F$, $\overline w$ increases when the rate
of unemployment compensation $c$ increases. Second, given $c$,
a mean-preserving increase in risk causes $\overline w$ to increase.
This second proposition follows directly from Figure \Fg{powdmt6f} %Figure 5.4
and the
characterization (iii) or (v) of a mean-preserving increase in risk.
From the definition of $g$ in equation \Ep{2.10} and the
characterization (iii) or (v), a mean-preserving spread
causes an upward shift in $\be(Ew-c)+\be g(w)$.
Since an increase in unemployment compensation and a mean-preserving
increase in risk both raise the reservation wage, it follows from the expression
for the value function in equation \Ep{2.15} that unemployed workers are
also better off with both such increases. It is obvious that an increase
in unemployment compensation raises the welfare of unemployed workers but
it might seem surprising that a mean-preserving increase in risk does too.
Intuition for this latter finding can be gleaned from the result in option
pricing theory that the value of an option is an increasing function of
the variance in the price of the underlying asset. This is so because
the option holder chooses to accept payoffs only from the right tail of
the distribution. In our context, the unemployed worker has the option
to accept a job and the asset value of a job offering wage rate $w$ is
equal to $w/(1-\beta)$.
%%(The ``exercise price'' for the unemployed worker is the loss of the
%%right to unemployment compensation.)
Under a mean-preserving increase in risk, the higher incidence of very
good wage offers increases the value of searching for a job while
the higher incidence of very bad wage offers is not detrimental because
the option to work will not be exercised at such low
wages.
\subsection{Allowing quits}\label{quits}%
Thus far, we have supposed that the worker cannot quit.
It happens that had we allowed the worker to
quit and search again, after being unemployed one period,
he would never exercise that option. To see this point,
recall that the reservation wage $\overline w$ in \Ep{2.15} satisfies
$$
v(\overline w) = {\overline w \over 1-\beta}= c+\beta \int v(w')dF(w'). \EQN res_wage
$$
Suppose the agent has in hand an offer to work at wage $w$.
Assuming that
the agent behaves optimally after any rejection of a wage $w$,
we can
compute the lifetime utility associated with
three mutually exclusive alternative ways of responding to that offer:
\medskip
\itemitem{A1. } Accept the wage and keep the job forever:
$$
{w \over 1-\beta}.
$$
\itemitem{A2. } Accept the wage but quit after $t$ periods:
$$
{w -\beta^t w \over 1 - \beta} +
\beta^t \left(c+\beta \int v(w')dF(w')\right)
= {w \over 1 - \beta} - \beta^t {w -\overline w \over 1 - \beta}.
$$
\itemitem{A3. } Reject the wage:
$$
c+\beta \int v(w')dF(w') = {\overline w \over 1-\beta}.
$$
\noindent
We conclude that if $w<\overline w$,
$$
A1 \prec A2 \prec A3,
$$
and if $w>\overline w$,
$$
A1 \succ A2 \succ A3.
$$
The three alternatives yield the same lifetime utility when $w=\overline w$.
\subsection{Waiting times}
It is straightforward to derive the probability distribution of the waiting
time until a job offer is accepted. Let $N$ be the random variable ``length of
time until a successful offer is encountered,'' with the understanding that
$N=1$ if the first job offer is accepted. Let $\la=\int_0^{\overline w} dF(w')$ be
the probability that a job offer is rejected. Then we have
Prob$\{N=1\}=(1-\la)$. The event that $N=2$ is the event that the first draw
is less than $\overline w$, which occurs with probability $\la$, and that the second
draw is greater than $\overline w$, which occurs with probability $(1-\la)$. By
virtue of the independence of successive draws, we have
Prob$\{N=2\}=(1-\la)\la$. More generally, Prob$\{N=j\}=(1-\la)\la^{j-1}$, so
the waiting time is geometrically distributed. The mean waiting time $\bar N$ is
given by
$$\eqalign{
\bar N &=\sum_{j=1}^\infty j\cdot\ {\rm Prob}\{N=j\}=\sum_{j=1}^\infty
j(1-\la)\la^{j-1}=(1-\lambda)\sum_{j=1}^\infty \sum_{k=1}^j
\lambda^{j-1} \cr
&=(1-\lambda)\sum_{k=0}^\infty \sum_{j=1}^\infty \lambda^{j-1+k}
=(1-\lambda)\sum_{k=0}^\infty \lambda^{k} (1-\lambda)^{-1}
=(1-\lambda)^{-1}.\cr}
$$
That is, the mean waiting
time to a successful job offer equals the reciprocal of the probability of
accepting an offer on a single trial.\NFootnote{An alternative way of deriving the mean
waiting time is to use the algebra of $z$ transforms. Define $h(z)=\sum_{j=0}^\infty h_jz^j$ and note
that $h'(z)=\sum_{j=1}^\infty j h_j z^{j-1}$ and
$h'(1)=\sum_{j=1}^\infty jh_j$. (For an introduction to $z$ transforms, see
Gabel and Roberts, 1973.) The $z$ transform of the sequence $(1-\la)\la^{j-1}$
is given by $\sum_{j=1}^\infty (1-\la)\la^{j-1} z^j=(1-\la)z/(1-\la z)$.
Evaluating $h'(z)$ at $z=1$ gives, after some simplification,
$h'(1)=1/(1-\la)$. Therefore, we have that the mean waiting time is
$(1-\la)\sum_{j=1}^\infty j\la^{j-1}=1/(1-\la)$.}
To illustrate the power of a recursive approach, we can also
compute the mean waiting time $\bar N$ as follows. First, because the environment is stationary
and associated with a constant
reservation wage and a constant probability of escaping unemployment, it
follows that in any period the ``remaining'' mean waiting time for all unemployed workers
equals $\bar N$. That is, all unemployed workers face
a mean waiting time of $\bar N$ regardless of
how long of an unemployment spell they have endured.
Second, the mean waiting time $\bar N$ must then be equal to the weighted
sum of two possible outcomes: either the worker accepts a job next period,
with probability $(1-\lambda)$; or she remains unemployed in the next
period, with probability $\lambda$. In the first case, the worker will have
ended her unemployment after one last period of unemployment while in the
second case, the worker will have suffered one period of unemployment {\it and}
will face a remaining mean waiting time of $\bar N$ periods. Hence, the
mean waiting time must satisfy:
$$
\bar N = (1-\lambda)\cdot 1 \,+\, \lambda \cdot (1 + \bar N)
\hskip1cm \Longrightarrow \hskip1cm \bar N = (1-\lambda)^{-1}.
$$
We invite the reader to prove that, given $F$, the mean waiting time
increases with increases in the rate of unemployment compensation, $c$.
\subsection{Firing}\label{firing}%
We now consider a modification of the job search model in which each
period after the first period on the job the worker faces probability
$\a$
of being fired, where
$1>\a>0$. The probability $\a$ of being fired next period is assumed to
be independent of tenure. A previously unemployed worker samples wage offers from a
time-invariant and known probability distribution $F$. Unemployed workers receive
unemployment compensation in the amount $c$. The worker receives a
time-invariant wage $w$ on a job until she is fired. A worker who is fired
becomes unemployed for one period before drawing a new wage. Only previously employed workers are fired.
A previously employed worker who is fired at the beginning of a period cannot draw a new wage offer that period but must
be unemployed for one period.
We let $\hat v(w)$ be the expected present value of income of a previously
unemployed worker who has offer $w$ in hand and who behaves optimally. If she
rejects the offer, she receives $c$ in unemployment compensation this period
and next period draws a new offer $w'$, whose value to her now is $\be \int
\hat v(w') dF(w')$. If she rejects the offer, $\hat v(w)=c+\be\int \hat v(w')dF(w')$.
If she
accepts the offer, she receives $w$ this period; next period with probability $1-\a $,
she is not fired and therefore what she receives is worth $\be \hat v(w)$ today;
with probability $\a$, she is fired next period, which has the consequence that after one period of
unemployment she draws a new wage, an outcome that today is worth $\be[c+ \be \int \hat v(w')dF(w')]$.
Therefore, if she accepts the offer,
$\hat v(w)=w+\be (1-\a)\hat v(w) + \be \a [c+ \be \int \hat v(w')dF(w')]$.
Thus, the Bellman equation becomes\NFootnote{If a worker who is fired at the beginning of a period were to have the opportunity to draw a new offer that same period,
then the Bellman equation would instead be
$$ \tilde v(w) = \max_{\rm accept, reject} \Bigl\{ w + \be (1-\a) \tilde v(w) + \beta \alpha \int \tilde v(w') d F(w'), c + \beta \int \tilde v(w') d F(w') \Bigr\} .$$}
$$\hat v(w)=\max_{\rm accept, reject} \Bigl\{w+\be (1-\a)\hat v(w) + \be \a [c+ \be E\hat v] ,\;
c+\be E\hat v\Bigr\},$$
where $E\hat v=\int \hat v(w')dF(w')$. Here the appearance of $\hat v(w)$ on the right side recognizes that if the worker had accepted wage offer $w$ last period with expected discounted present value $\hat v(w)$,
the stationarity of the problem (i.e., the fact that $F, \alpha, c $ are all fixed) makes $\hat v(w)$ also be the continuation value associated with retaining this job next period.
This equation has a solution of the
form\NFootnote{That it
takes this form can be established by guessing
that $\hat v(w)$ is nondecreasing in $w$. This guess implies the
equation in the text for $\hat v(w)$, which is nondecreasing in $w$.
This argument verifies that $\hat v(w)$ is nondecreasing, given the
uniqueness of the solution of the Bellman equation.}
%$$\def\apricot{{\eqalign{ {w+\be\a [c+\be Ev]\over 1-\be(1-\a)},&\qquad
% w\ge \overline w\cr
%c+\be Ev,& \qquad w\le \overline w,\cr}}}
%v(w)=\left\{\apricot\right.$$
%$$
$$\hat v(w) = \cases{{\displaystyle w+\be\a [c+\be E\hat v]\over \displaystyle 1-\be(1-\a)},&
if $w\ge \overline w $ \cr
\Big. c+\be E\hat v,& $w\le \overline w $\cr}$$
where $\overline w$ solves
$${\overline w+\be \alpha [c+\be E\hat v]\over 1-\be(1-\a)} =c+\be E\hat v, $$
which can be rearranged as
$$
{\overline w \over 1-\beta } = %c+\be E\hat v =
c+\beta \int \hat v(w')dF(w'). \EQN firewbar
$$
We can compare the reservation wage in \Ep{firewbar} to the
reservation wage in expression \Ep{res_wage} when there was no risk of
being fired. The two expressions look identical but the reservation
wages differ because the value functions differ.
In particular, $\hat v(w)$ is strictly
less than $v(w)$. This is an immediate implication of our argument that it
cannot be optimal to quit if you have accepted a wage strictly
greater than the reservation wage in the situation without possible firings
(see section \use{quits}). So even though workers who face no possible firings can mimic outcomes
in situations where they would facing possible firings by
occasionally ``firing themselves'' by quitting into unemployment, they choose
not to do so because that would lower their expected present value of income. Since the
employed workers in the situation where they face possible firings are worse off than
employed workers in the situation without possible firings, it follows that $\hat v(w)$
lies strictly below $v(w)$ over the whole domain because, even at wages
that are rejected, the value function partly reflects a stream of future outcomes whose
expectation is less favorable in the situation in which workers face a chance of
being fired.
Since the value function $\hat v(w)$ with firings lies
strictly below the value function $v(w)$ without firings,
it follows from \Ep{firewbar} and \Ep{res_wage} that the reservation
wage $\overline w$ is strictly lower with firings.
There is less of a reason to hold out for high-paying jobs when a job
is expected to last for a shorter period of time.
That is, unemployed workers optimally invest less in search when the
payoffs associated with wage offers
have gone down because of the probability of being fired.
%The optimal policy is of the reservation wage form. The reservation
%wage $\overline
%w$ will not be characterized here as a function of $c$, $F$, and $\a$;
%the reader is invited to do so by pursuing the implications of the preceding
%formula.
% If she
%accepts the offer, she receives $w$ this period, with probability $\a $ that
%she is fired and must draw again next period receiving $\be\int v(w')dF(w')$
%and with probability $(1-\a)$ that she is not fired, in which case
%she receives
%$\be v(w)$. Therefore, if she accepts the offer, $v(w)=w+\be \a\int
%v(w')dF(w')+\be (1-\a)v(w)$. Thus the Bellman equation becomes
%$$v(w)=\max \{w+ \be\a Ev+\be (1-\a) v(w),c+\be Ev\},$$
%where $Ev=\int v(w')dF(w')$. This equation has a solution of the
%form\NFootnote{That it takes this form can be established by guessing
%that $v(w)$ is nondecreasing in $w$. This guess implies the
%equation in the text for $v(w)$, which is nondecreasing in $w$.
%This argument verifies that $v(w)$ is nondecreasing, given the
%uniqueness of the solution of the Bellman equation.}
%$$\def\apricot{{\eqalign{ {w+\be\a Ev\over 1-\be(1-\a)},&\qquad
% w\ge \overline w\cr
%c+\be Ev,& \qquad w\le \overline w,\cr}}}
%v(w)=\left\{\apricot\right.$$
%where $\overline w$ solves
%$${\overline w+\be \alpha Ev\over 1-\be(1-\a)} =c+\be Ev.$$
%The optimal policy is of the reservation wage form. The reservation wage
%$\overline
%w$ will not be characterized here as a function of $c$, $F$, and $\a$;
%the reader is invited to do so by pursuing the implications of the preceding
%formula.
\section{A lake model}
Consider an economy consisting of a continuum of {\it ex ante\/}
identical workers living in the environment described in the previous
section. These workers move recurrently between unemployment
and employment.
The mean duration of each spell of employment
is $\alpha^{-1}$ and the mean duration of unemployment
is $[1 - F(\overline w)]^{-1}$. The average unemployment rate
$U_t$
across the continuum of workers obeys the difference equation
$$ U_{t+1} = \alpha (1 - U_t ) + F(\overline w) U_t , $$
where $\alpha$ is the hazard rate \index{hazard rate} of escaping employment
and $[1 - F(\overline w)]$ is the hazard rate of escaping unemployment.
Solving this difference equation for a stationary solution, i.e., imposing
$U_{t+1} = U_t = U$, gives
$$ U ={\alpha \over \alpha + 1 - F (\overline w) } \hskip1cm \Longrightarrow
\hskip1cm
U = {\displaystyle {1 \over 1 - F(\overline w)} \over
\displaystyle { 1 \over 1 - F(\overline w)} + {1 \over \alpha} } .
\EQN Ulake $$
Equation \Ep{Ulake} expresses the stationary unemployment rate in terms
of the ratio of the average duration of unemployment to the
sum of average durations of unemployment and employment. The
unemployment rate, being an average across workers at each moment,
thus reflects the average
outcomes experienced by workers {\it across time}.
This way of linking economy-wide averages at a point in time with the
time-series average for a representative worker is our first
encounter with a class of models sometimes referred to as
Bewley models, which we shall study in depth in chapter \use{incomplete}.
\index{Bewley models}
This model of unemployment is sometimes called a lake model and
can be depicted as in Figure \Fg{lake1f}, %Figure 5.5
with two lakes denoted
$U$ and $1-U$ representing volumes of unemployment and employment, and streams
of rate $\alpha$ from the $1-U$ lake to the $U$ lake
and of rate $1-F(\overline w)$ from
the $U$ lake to the $1-U$ lake. Equation \Ep{Ulake} allows us to
study the determinants of the unemployment rate in
terms of the hazard rate of becoming unemployed $\alpha$ and
the hazard rate of escaping unemployment $1 - F(\overline w)$.
%%%%%%%
%$$
%\grafone{lake1.eps,height=1.5in}{{\bf Figure 5.5} Lake model
%with flows $\alpha$ from employment state $1-U$ to unemployment
%state $U$ and $[1-F(\overline w)]$ from $U$ to $1-U$.}
%$$
%%%%%%%%%%
\midfigure{lake1f}
\centerline{\epsfxsize=3truein\epsffile{lake1.eps}}
\caption{Lake model with flows of rate $\alpha$ from employment state $1-U$ to
unemployment state $U$ and of rate $[1-F(\overline w)]$ from $U$ to $1-U$.}
\infiglist{Lake model}
\endfigure
\section{A model of career choice}
\auth{Neal, Derek}%
This section describes a model of occupational choice that
Derek Neal (1999) used to understand employment histories
of recent high school graduates. Neal wanted to explain
why young men often switch jobs {\it and\/} careers early in their
work histories, then later focus their searches for jobs within a single
career, and finally settle down in a particular
job. Neal's model can be regarded
as a simplified version of Brian McCall's (1991) model.
\auth{McCall, B. P.}
A worker chooses career-job $(\theta,\epsilon)$ pairs
subject to the following conditions: There is no
unemployment. The worker's earnings
at time $t$ equal $\theta_t + \epsilon_t$, where $\theta_t$ is a component specific to a {\it career\/}
and ${\epsilon_t}$ is a component specific to a particular {\it job}. The worker
maximizes $E \sum_{t=0}^\infty \beta^t (\theta_t + \epsilon_t).$
A {\it career\/} is a draw
of $\theta$ from c.d.f.\ $F$; a {\it job\/} is a draw of
$\epsilon$ from c.d.f.\ $G$. Successive draws are independent,
and $G(0)=F(0)=0$, $G(B_\epsilon)= F(B_\theta)=1$. The
worker can draw a new career only if he also draws a
new job.
However, the worker is free to retain his existing
career $\theta$, and to draw a new job $\epsilon'$. The worker
decides at the beginning of a period whether to stay in a
career-job pair inherited from the past, stay in an inherited career but
draw a new job, or draw a new career-job pair. There is
no opportunity to recall past jobs or careers.
Let $v(\theta,\epsilon)$ be the optimal value of the problem
at the beginning of a period
for a worker currently having inherited career-job pair $(\theta,\epsilon)$ and
who is about to decide whether to draw a new career and or job.
The value function $v(\theta,\epsilon)$ satisfies the Bellman equation
$$\EQNalign{
v(\theta,\epsilon) = \max &\left\{
\theta + \epsilon + \beta v(\theta,\epsilon),\;
\theta + \int \left[\epsilon' + \beta v(\theta, \epsilon')\right]
d\, G(\epsilon'), \right. \cr
& \left. \int \int \left[ \theta' + \epsilon' + \beta v(\theta', \epsilon')
\right]
d \, F(\theta') d \, G(\epsilon') \right\}. \EQN s_val}$$
%{\eightpoint
%$$ v(\theta,\epsilon) = \max \left\{
% \theta + \epsilon + \beta v(\theta,\epsilon), \theta + \epsilon
% + \beta \int v(\theta, \epsilon') d\, G(\epsilon'),
% \theta + \epsilon + \beta \int v(\theta', \epsilon') d \, F(\theta')
% d \, G(\epsilon') \right\},$$
%} % endeightpoint
\noindent
Maximization is over three possible actions: (1) retain
the present job-career pair; (2) retain the present career but
draw a new job; and (3) draw both a new job and a new career. We might nickname these
three alternatives `stay put', `new job', `new life'.
The value function is increasing in both $\theta$ and $\epsilon$.
Figures \Fg{neal1newaf} and \Fg{neal2newaf} % Figures 5.6 and 5.7
display the optimal value function
and the optimal decision rule for Neal's model
where $F$ and $G$ are each distributed according to discrete
uniform
distributions on $[0, 5]$ with 50 evenly distributed discrete values for
each of $\theta$ and $\epsilon$ and $\beta = .95$. We computed
the value function
by iterating to convergence on the Bellman equation.
The optimal policy is characterized by three regions in the $(\theta,
\epsilon)$ space. For high enough values of $\epsilon+\theta$,
the worker stays put.
For high $\theta$ but low $\epsilon$, the worker retains his
career but searches for a better job. For low values of $\theta + \epsilon$,
the worker finds a new career and a new job. In figures \Fg{neal1newaf} and \Fg{neal2newaf}, the decision to {\it retain\/} both job and career occurs
in the high $\theta$, high $\epsilon$ region of the state space; the decision to retain career $\theta$ but search for a new job $\epsilon'$
occurs in the high $\theta$ and low $\epsilon$ region of the state space; and the decision to `get a new life' by drawing both a new $\theta'$ and a new $\epsilon'$ occurs in the low $\theta$, low $\epsilon$ region.\NFootnote{The computations were
performed by the Matlab program {\tt neal2.m}.}
\mtlb{neal2.m}
%%%%%%%%
%$$
%\grafone{neal1newa.eps,height=2.25in}{{\bf Figure 5.6} Optimal value
%function for Neal's model with $\beta=.95$. The value function is
%flat in the reject $(\theta,\epsilon)$ region, increasing in
%$\theta$ only in the keep-career-but-draw-new-job region,
%and increasing in both $\theta$ and $\epsilon$ in the stay-put region.}
%$$
%%%%%%%%%
\midfigure{neal1newaf}
\centerline{\epsfxsize=3truein\epsffile{neal1newa.eps}}
\caption{Optimal value function for Neal's model with $\beta=.95$. The value
function is flat in the reject $(\theta,\epsilon)$ region; increasing in
$\theta$ only in the keep-career-but-draw-new-job region; and increasing in
both $\theta$ and $\epsilon$ in the stay-put region.}
\infiglist{Neal 1}
\endfigure
%%%%%%%%%
%$$\grafone{neal2newa.eps,height=2.25in}{{\bf Figure 5.7} Optimal decision
%rule for Neal's model. For $(\theta, \epsilon)$'s
%within the white area, the worker changes both
%jobs and careers. In the gray area, the worker retains his career
%but draws a new job. The worker accepts $(\theta,\epsilon)$ in
%the black area.}
%$$
%%%%%%%%
\midfigure{neal2newaf}
\centerline{\epsfxsize=3truein\epsffile{neal2newa.eps}}
\caption{Optimal decision rule for Neal's model. For $(\theta, \epsilon)$'s
within the white area, the worker changes both jobs and careers. In the grey
area, the worker retains his career but draws a new job. The worker accepts
$(\theta,\epsilon)$ in the black area.}
\infiglist{Neal 2}
\endfigure
When the career-job pair $(\theta, \epsilon)$ is such that the worker
chooses to stay put, the value function in \Ep{s_val} attains the
value $(\theta + \epsilon)/(1-\beta)$. Of course, this happens when
the decision to stay put weakly dominates the other two actions, which
occurs when
$$ {\theta + \epsilon \over 1 - \beta} \geq \max\left\{
C(\theta), Q\right\}, \EQN compar1 $$
where $Q$ is the value of drawing both a new job and a new career,
$$ Q \equiv \int \int \left[ \theta' + \epsilon' +
\beta v(\theta', \epsilon')\right]
d \, F(\theta') d \, G(\epsilon'), $$
and $C(\theta)$ is the value of keeping $\theta$ but drawing a new job $\epsilon'$:
$$C(\theta)= \theta + \int \left[\epsilon' + \beta v(\theta, \epsilon')\right]
d\, G(\epsilon').$$
For a given career $\theta$, a job $\overline \epsilon
(\theta) $
makes equation \Ep{compar1} hold with equality. Evidently,
$\overline \epsilon(\theta)$ solves
$$ \overline\epsilon(\theta) = \max [ (1-\beta) C(\theta) - \theta,
(1-\beta) Q - \theta]. $$
The decision to stay put is optimal
for any career-job pair $(\theta, \epsilon)$ that satisfies
$\epsilon \geq \overline
\epsilon(\theta)$. When this condition is not satisfied,
the worker will draw either a new career-job pair $(\theta', \epsilon')$ or
only a new job $\epsilon'$.
Retaining a career $\theta$
is optimal when
$$
C(\theta) \geq Q. \EQN s_career
$$
We can solve \Ep{s_career} for the critical career value
$\overline \theta$ satisfying
$$ C( \overline \theta ) = Q . \EQN overtheta $$
Thus, independently of $\epsilon$, the worker will never abandon any
career $\theta \geq \overline \theta$. The decision rule for accepting
the current career can thus be expressed as follows:
accept the current career $\theta$ if $\theta \geq \overline \theta $
or if the current career-job pair $(\theta, \epsilon)$ satisfies
$\epsilon \geq \overline \epsilon(\theta)$.
We can say more about the cutoff value $\overline \epsilon(\theta)$
in the retain-$\theta$ region $\theta \geq \overline \theta$.
When $\theta \geq \overline \theta$, because we know that the
worker will keep $\theta$ forever, it follows that
$$ C(\theta) = {\theta \over 1 -\beta} + \int J(\epsilon')
d G(\epsilon'), $$
where $J(\epsilon)$ is the optimal value of % the $epsilon$-component
$ \sum_{t=0}^\infty \beta^t \epsilon_t$ for a worker who has already decided to keep
career $\theta$, who
has just drawn $\epsilon$, and who can draw a new job $\epsilon'$ next period.
The Bellman equation for $J$ is
$$ J(\epsilon) = \max \left\{ {\epsilon \over 1-\beta},
\epsilon + \beta \int J(\epsilon') d G(\epsilon')\right\} .
\EQN littlebell $$
This resembles the Bellman equation for the optimal value function for the
basic McCall model, with a slight modification.
The optimal policy is of the reservation-job form: keep the job $\epsilon$
if $\epsilon \geq \overline \epsilon$, otherwise try a new job next
period.
The absence of $\theta$ from \Ep{littlebell} implies that
in the range $\theta \geq \overline \theta$, $\overline \epsilon$
is independent of $\theta$.
These results explain some features of the value function
plotted in Figure \Fg{neal1newaf} %Figure 5.6.
At the boundary separating
the ``new life'' and ``new job'' regions of the $(\theta, \epsilon)$
plane, equation \Ep{overtheta} is satisfied. At the boundary
separating the ``new job'' and ``stay put'' regions,
$ {\theta + \epsilon \over 1 - \beta} = C(\theta) =
{\theta \over 1-\beta} + \int J(\epsilon') d G(\epsilon')$.
Finally, between the ``new life'' and ``stay put'' regions,
${\theta + \epsilon \over 1 - \beta} = Q$, which defines
a diagonal line in the $(\theta, \epsilon)$ plane (see Figure
\Fg{neal2newaf}). % Figure 5.7).
The value function
is the constant value $Q$
in the ``get a new life'' region (i.e., the region in which the optimal decision is to draw a new $(\theta,\epsilon)$
pair). Equation \Ep{s_career} helps
us understand why there is a set of high $\theta$'s in Figure \Fg{neal2newaf} % Figure 5.7
for which $v(\theta,\epsilon)$ rises with $\theta$ but
is flat with respect to $\epsilon$.
Probably the most interesting feature of the model is that it is possible
to draw a $(\theta, \epsilon)$ pair that makes
the value of keeping the career ($\theta$) and drawing a new
job match ($\epsilon'$) exceed both the value of
stopping search and the value of starting again to
search from the beginning by drawing a new $(\theta', \epsilon')$ pair.
This outcome occurs when a large $\theta$ is drawn with a small
$\epsilon$. In this case, it can occur that $\theta \geq \overline
\theta$ and
$\epsilon < \overline \epsilon(\theta)$.\NFootnote{Pavan (2011) builds on Neal's model
in interesting ways.} \auth{Pavan, Ronni}
Viewed as a normative model for young workers, Neal's model tells them:
don't shop for a firm until you have found a career you like.
As a positive model, it predicts that workers will not
switch careers after they have settled on one. Neal presents
data indicating that while this stark prediction does not hold up perfectly, it
is a good first approximation.
He suggests that extending the model to include learning, along the
lines of Jovanovic's model to be described in section \use{sec:Jov},
could help explain the later career switches that
his model misses.\NFootnote{Neal's model can be used to deduce waiting times
to the event $(\theta \geq \overline \theta) \cup (\epsilon \geq \overline
\epsilon(\theta))$.
The first event within the union is choosing
a career that is never abandoned. The second event
is choosing a permanent job.
Neal used the model to approximate and
interpret observed career and job switches of young workers.}
%\note{Neal's model can be used to deduce waiting times
%to the event $(\theta \geq \overline \theta) \cup [{\theta + \epsilon \over
%1 - \beta}
%\geq \int v(\theta, \epsilon') d \, G(\epsilon')]$ and the
%event $[{\theta+ \epsilon \over 1 - \beta} \geq \int
%v(\theta,\epsilon') d \, G(\epsilon')) \cup ( \int v(\theta,\epsilon')
%d \, G(\epsilon') \geq Q]$.
% The first event is choosing
%a career. The second is choosing a job, conditional on having selected
%a career.
%Neal used the model to approximate and
%interpret observed career and job switches of young workers.}
\section{Offer distribution unknown}\label{sec:Offer_distribution}%
Consider the following modification of the McCall search model.
An unemployed worker wants to maximize the expected present value of
$\sum_{t=0}^\infty \beta^t y_t$ where $y_t$ equals wage $w$ when employed and unemployment compensation $c$ when unemployed.
Each period the worker receives one offer to work forever at a wage $w$ drawn from one of two
cumulative distribution functions $F$ or $G$, where $F(0)=G(0) = 0$ and $F(B) = G(B) = 1$ for $B > 0$.
Nature draws from the same distribution, either $F$ or $G$, at all dates and the worker knows this, but he or she does not know whether it is $F$ or $G$.
At time $0$ {\it before\/} drawing a wage offer, the worker attaches probability $\pi_{-1} \in (0,1)$ to the distribution being
$F$. We assume that the distributions have densities $f$ and $g$, respectively, and that they have common support.
Before drawing a wage at time $0$, the worker thus believes that the density of $w_0$
is $h(w_0;\pi_{-1}) = \pi_{-1} f(w_0) + (1-\pi_{-1}) g(w_0) $. After drawing $w_0$, the worker uses Bayes' law to deduce that
the posterior probability that the density is $f(w)$ is\NFootnote{The worker's initial beliefs induce a joint probability distribution
over a potentially infinite sequence of draws $w_0, w_1, \ldots $. Bayes' law is simply an application of the laws of
probability to compute the conditional distribution of the $t$th draw $w_t$ conditional on $[w_0, \ldots, w_{t-1}]$. Since we assume from the start that the decision maker {\it knows\/} the joint distribution and the laws of probability, one respectable view is that Bayes' law is less a `theory of learning' than a statement about the consequences of information inflows for a decision maker who thinks he knows the truth (i.e., a joint probability distribution) from the beginning.}\index{Bayes' Law!with search model}%
$$\pi_0 = { \pi_{-1} f(w_0) \over \pi_{-1} f(w_0) + (1-\pi_{-1}) g(w_0)} .$$
More generally, after observing $w_t$ for the $t$th draw, the worker believes that
the probability that $w_{t+1}$ is to be drawn from distribution $F$ is
$$ \pi_t = { \pi_{t-1} f(w_t)/g(w_t) \over \pi_{t-1} f(w_t)/g(w_t) + (1-\pi_{t-1})} \EQN update1 $$
and that the density of $w_{t+1}$ is
$$h(w_{t+1};\pi_{t}) = \pi_{t} f(w_{t+1}) + (1-\pi_{t}) g(w_{t+1}) . \EQN distribut_t$$
\offparens
Notice that
$$ \eqalign{ E(\pi_t | \pi_{t-1}) & = \int \Bigl[ { \pi_{t-1} f(w) \over \pi_{t-1} f(w) + (1-\pi_{t-1})g(w) } \Bigr]
\Bigl[ \pi_{t-1} f(w) + (1-\pi_{t-1})g(w) \Bigr] d w \cr
& = \pi_{t-1} \int f(w) dw \cr
& = \pi_{t-1}, \cr}$$
\autoparens
so that the process $\pi_t$ is a {\it martingale\/} bounded by $0$ and $1$. (In the first line in the above string of equalities, the term in the first set of brackets
is just $\pi_t$ as a function of $w_{t}$, while the term in the second set of brackets is the density of $w_{t}$ conditional
on $\pi_{t-1}$.) Notice that here we are computing $E(\pi_t | \pi_{t-1})$ under the subjective density described in the second
term in brackets. It follows from the martingale convergence theorem (see appendix A %\use{app:Ach16}
of chapter \use{selfinsure}) that $\pi_t$ converges almost surely to a random variable in $[0,1]$. Practically, this means that probability one is attached to sample paths
$\{\pi_t\}_{t=0}^\infty$ that converge. However, different sample paths can converge to different limiting values.
The limit points of $\{\pi_t\}_{t=0}^\infty$ as $t \rightarrow +\infty$ thus constitute a random variable with what is in general a non-trivial distribution. \index{martingale!convergence theorem}%
Let $v(w_t,\pi_t)$ be the optimal value of the problem for a previously unemployed worker who has just drawn
$w$ and updated $\pi$ according to \Ep{update1}. The Bellman equation is
$$ v(w, \pi_t) = \max_{{\rm accept, reject}} \biggl\{ {w \over 1-\beta}, c
+ \beta \int v(w', \pi_{t+1}(w')) h(w'; \pi_t) d w' \biggr\} \EQN Bellman_unknown$$
subject to \Ep{update1} and \Ep{distribut_t}.
The state vector is the worker's current draw $w$ and his post-draw estimate of the probability that the distribution is
$f$. The second term on the right side of \Ep{Bellman_unknown} integrates the value function evaluated at next period's state vector with respect to the worker's subjective
distribution $h(w'; \pi_t)$ of next period's draw $w'$. The value function for next period recognizes
that $\pi_{t+1}$ will be updated in a way that depends on $w'$ via Bayes' law as captured by equation \Ep{update1}.
\auth{Jovanovic, Boyan}%
Evidently, the optimal policy is to set a reservation wage $\bar w(\pi_t)$ that depends on $\pi_t$.
As an example, we have computed the optimal policy by backward induction assuming that $f$ is a uniform distribution
on $[0, 2]$ while $g$ is a beta distribution with parameters (3,1.2).\NFootnote{The beta distribution for $w$ is characterized by
a density $g(w;\alpha, \gamma) \propto w^{\alpha-1}(1-w)^{(\gamma-1)}$, where the factor of proportionality is chosen to make the
density integrate to 1.} \index{beta distribution}%
We set unemployment compensation $c=.6$ and
the discount factor $\beta=.95$.\NFootnote{The matlab programs
{\tt search\_learn\_francisco\_3.m} and {\tt search\_learn\_beta\_2.m} perform these calculations.} The two densities are plotted
in figure \Fg{two_densities}, which shows that the $g$ density provides better prospects for the worker than
does the uniform $f$ density. It stands to reason that the worker's reservation wage falls as the posterior
probability $\pi$ that he places on density $f$ rises, as figure \Fg{reservation_wage_pi} confirms.
%\mtlb{search\_learn\_francisco_3.m}%
\mtlb{search\_learn\_francisco\_3.m}%
\mtlb{search\_learn\_beta\_2.m}%
\midfigure{two_densities}
\centerline{\epsfxsize=3true in\epsffile{two_densities.eps}}
\caption{Two densities for wages, a uniform $f(w)$ and $g(w)$ that is a beta distribution
with parameters 3, 1.2.}
\infiglist{two_densities}
\endfigure