-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 1
/
Copy pathblack0.tex
1143 lines (1042 loc) · 56 KB
/
black0.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
%\eqnotracetrue
%\pageno=3
\footnum=0
\chapter{Overview\label{overview}}%
\section{Warning}
This chapter provides a nontechnical summary of some themes of
this book.
We debated whether to put this chapter first or last. A way to use this
chapter is to read it twice, once before reading anything else in the book,
then again after having mastered the techniques presented in the rest of the book.
That second time, this chapter will be easy and enjoyable reading,
and it will remind you of connections that transcend a variety of apparently disparate
topics. But on first reading, this chapter will be difficult, partly because
the discussion is mainly literary and therefore incomplete. Measure
what you have learned by comparing your understandings after those first
and second readings. Or just skip this chapter and read it after
the others.
\section{A common ancestor}
Clues in our mitochondrial DNA tell biologists that we humans
share a common ancestor called Eve who lived 100,000 years ago.
All of macroeconomics too seems to have descended from a
common source, Irving Fisher's and Milton Friedman's
consumption Euler
equation, the cornerstone of
the permanent income theory of consumption.
Modern macroeconomics records the fruits and frustrations of a long
love-hate affair with the permanent income mechanism. As a way of
summarizing some important themes in our book, we briefly
chronicle some of the high and low points of this long affair.
\section{The savings problem}
A consumer wants to maximize
$$E_0 \sum_{t=0}^\infty \beta^t u(c_t) \EQN sintro2 $$
where $\beta \in (0,1)$, $u$ is a twice continuously
differentiable, increasing, strictly concave utility function, and
$E_0$ denotes a mathematical expectation conditioned on time $0$
information. The consumer faces a sequence of budget
constraints\NFootnote{We use a different notation in chapter
\use{selfinsure}: $A_t$ here conforms to $-b_t$ in chapter \use{selfinsure}.}
$$ A_{t+1} = R_{t+1} (A_t + y_t -c_t) \EQN sintro3 $$
for $t\geq 0$,
where $A_{t+1} \geq \underline A$ is the consumer's holdings of an asset at the beginning
of period $t+1$, $\underline A$ is a lower bound on asset holdings,
$y_t$ is a random endowment sequence, $c_t$ is consumption
of a single good, and $R_{t+1}$ is the gross rate of return on the asset
between $t$ and $t+1$. In the general version of the problem,
both $R_{t+1}$ and $y_t$ can be random, though special cases of the
problem restrict $R_{t+1}$ further.
A first-order necessary condition for this problem is
$$ \beta E_t R_{t+1} {u'(c_{t+1}) \over u'(c_t)} \leq 1, \quad
= \ {\rm if} \ A_{t+1} > \underline A. \EQN sintro1 $$
This Euler inequality recurs as either the cornerstone or the
straw man in many theories
contained in this book.
Different modeling choices
put \Ep{sintro1} to work in different ways. One
can restrict $u, \beta$, the return process
$R_{t+1}$, the lower bound on assets $\underline A$,
the income process $y_t$, and the consumption
process $c_t$ in various ways.
By making alternative choices about restrictions
to impose on subsets of these objects, macroeconomists have constructed
theories about consumption, asset prices, and the distribution of
wealth. Alternative versions of equation \Ep{sintro1} also underlie Chamley's (1986)
and Judd's (1985b)
striking
results about eventually not taxing capital.
\subsection{Linear quadratic permanent income theory}
To obtain a version of the permanent income theory of
Friedman (1955) and Hall (1978), set $R_{t+1} =R$, impose
$R=\beta^{-1}$, assume the quadratic utility function
$u(c_t)=-(c_t-\gamma)^2$, and allow consumption $c_t$ to
be negative. We also allow
%%that $u $ is quadratic so that $u'$ is linear.
%%Allow
$\{y_t\}$ to be an arbitrary stationary
process, and dispense with the lower bound $\underline A$.
The Euler inequality \Ep{sintro1} then implies that consumption is
a martingale:
$$ E_t c_{t+1} = c_t. \EQN sintro4 $$
Subject to a boundary condition that\NFootnote{The motivation for
using this boundary condition instead of a lower bound $\underline
A$ on asset holdings is that there is no ``natural'' lower bound on
asset holdings when consumption is permitted to be negative.
%%, as it is when $u$ is quadratic in $c$.
Chapters \use{recurge} and \use{incomplete}
discuss what are called ``natural borrowing limits,''
the lowest possible appropriate values of $\underline A$ in the case
that $c$ is nonnegative.}
$E_0 \sum_{t=0}^\infty \beta^t A_t^2 <\infty$,
equation \Ep{sintro4} and the budget constraints \Ep{sintro3} can be solved
to yield
$$ c_t = \left[{r \over 1+r}\right]
\left[E_t \sum_{j=0}^\infty
\left({1 \over 1+r}\right)^j y_{t+j} + A_t \right]
\EQN sintro5 $$
where $1+r = R$. Equation \Ep{sintro5}
expresses consumption as a fixed marginal propensity to consume
${r \over 1+r}$ that is applied to the sum of human wealth -- namely
$\left[E_t \sum_{j=0}^\infty
\left({1 \over 1+r}\right)^j y_{t+j}\right] $ -- and
financial wealth, $A)t$.
This equation has the following notable features:
(1) consumption is smoothed on average across time: current
consumption depends only on the expected present value of nonfinancial
income;
(2) feature (1) opens the way to Ricardian equivalence: redistributions
of lump-sum taxes over time that leave the expected present value of
nonfinancial income unaltered do not affect consumption;
(3) there is certainty equivalence: increases in the conditional variances
of future incomes about their forecast values do not affect consumption
(though they do diminish the consumer's utility);
(4) a by-product of certainty equivalence is that the marginal propensities
to consume out of financial and nonfinancial wealth are equal.
\auth{Ligon, Ethan} \auth{Blundell, Richard}
\auth{Preston, Ian}%
This theory continues to be a workhorse in much
good applied work (see Ligon (1998)
and Blundell and
Preston (1999) for creative applications).
Chapter \use{dplinear} describes conditions under which
certainty equivalence prevails, while chapters \use{timeseries} and \use{dplinear}
also describe the structure of the cross-equation
restrictions that the hypothesis of rational expectations imposes and that
empirical studies
heavily exploit.
\subsection{Precautionary saving}\label{sec:intro_precautionary}%
A literature on ``the savings problem'' or ``precautionary saving''
investigates the consequences of altering the assumption in the
linear quadratic permanent income theory that $u$
is quadratic, an assumption that makes the marginal utility of consumption
become negative for large enough $c$. Rather than assuming that
$u$ is quadratic, the literature on the savings problem
assumes that $u$ is increasing and strictly
concave. This assumption keeps the marginal utility of
consumption above zero. We retain other features of the
linear quadratic model ($\beta R=1$, $\{y_t\}$ is a stationary
process), but now impose a borrowing limit $A_t \geq \underline
a$.
With these assumptions, something amazing occurs: Euler
inequality \Ep{sintro1} implies that the marginal utility of
consumption is a {\it nonnegative\/}
supermartingale.\NFootnote{See chapter \use{selfinsure}. The situation
is simplest in the case that the $y_t$ process is i.i.d. so that
the value function can be expressed as a function of level $y_t +
A_t$ alone: $V(A+y)$. Applying the Benveniste-Scheinkman formula
from chapter \use{dynamicdp1} shows
that $V'(A+y)=u'(c)$, which implies that when $\beta
R=1$, \Ep{sintro1} becomes $E_t V'(A_{t+1}+y_{t+1}) \leq
V'(A_t+y_t)$,
which states that
the derivative of the value function is a nonnegative supermartingale.
%which shows that where $V(a)$ is the value function for the saving
%problem with an i.i.d.\ endowment, condition \Ep{sintro1}
%implies that $V'(a)$ is a nonnegative martingale,
That in turn implies
that $A$ almost surely diverges to $+\infty$.} That gives the
model the striking implication that $c_t \rightarrow_{as} +\infty$
and $A_t \rightarrow_{as} +\infty$, where $\rightarrow_{as}$ means
almost sure convergence. Consumption and wealth will fluctuate
randomly in response to income fluctuations, but so long as
randomness in income continues,
they will drift upward over time without bound.
If
randomness eventually expires in the tail of the income
process, then both consumption
and income converge. But even
small perpetual random fluctuations
in income are enough to cause both consumption and assets to diverge
to $+\infty$. This response
of the optimal consumption
plan to randomness is required by the Euler equation \Ep{sintro1} and
is called precautionary savings.
By keeping the marginal utility of consumption positive,
precautionary savings models arrest the certainty equivalence that prevails
in the linear quadratic permanent income model.
Chapter \use{selfinsure} studies the savings problem in depth and struggles
to understand the workings of the powerful martingale convergence theorem.
The supermartingale convergence theorem also plays an important role in the model
insurance with private information in chapter \use{socialinsurance}.
\subsection{Complete markets, insurance, and the distribution of wealth}\label{sec:intro_complete}%
To build a model of the distribution of wealth, we consider a setting
with many consumers.
To start, imagine a large number of {\it ex ante\/}
identical consumers with preferences \Ep{sintro2} who are allowed
to share their income risk by trading one-period contingent
claims. For simplicity, assume that the saving possibility
represented by the budget constraint \Ep{sintro3} is no longer available\NFootnote{It
can be shown that even if it were available, people would not want
to use it.} but that it is replaced by access to an extensive set
of insurance markets. Assume that household $i$ has an income
process $y_t^i = g_i(s_t)$ where $s_t$ is a state vector governed
by a Markov process with transition density $\pi(s'|s)$, where $s$ and $s'$
are elements of a common state space ${\bf S}$. (See
chapters \use{timeseries} and \use{recurge} for material about Markov
chains and their uses in equilibrium models.) Each period every household can trade
one-period state-contingent claims to consumption next period.
Let $Q(s'|s)$ be the price of one unit of consumption next period
in state $s'$ when the state this period is $s$. When household
$i$ has the opportunity to trade such state-contingent securities,
its first-order conditions for maximizing \Ep{sintro2} are
$$ Q(s_{t+1}|s_t) = \beta {u'(c^i_{t+1}(s_{t+1}))\over u'(c^i_t(s_t)) }
\pi(s_{t+1}|s_t) .
\EQN sintro15 $$
Notice that $\int_{s_{t+1}} Q(s_{t+1} | s_t) d s_{t+1}$
is the price of a risk-free claim on consumption one period ahead: it is
thus the reciprocal of the gross risk-free interest rate $R$. Therefore, if we sum
both sides of \Ep{sintro15} over $s_{t+1}$, we obtain our standard
consumption Euler condition \Ep{sintro1} at
equality.\NFootnote{That the asset is risk-free becomes manifested
in $R_{t+1}$ being a function of $s_t$, so that it is known at
$t$.} Thus, the complete markets equation \Ep{sintro15} is
consistent with our complete markets Euler equation \Ep{sintro1}, but \Ep{sintro15}
imposes more. We will exploit
this fact extensively in chapter \use{optax}.
In a widely studied special case, there is no aggregate risk, so
that $\int_{i} y_t^i d \, i = \int_i g_i(s_t) d \, i = {\rm constant}$.
In that case, it can be shown that the competitive equilibrium
state-contingent prices become
$$ Q(s_{t+1} | s_t) = \beta \pi(s_{t+1} | s_t) . \EQN sintro16 $$
This, in turn, implies that the risk-free
gross rate of return $R$ is $\beta^{-1}$.\NFootnote{This follows because the
price of a risk-free claim to consumption tomorrow at date $t$ in state $s_t$ is $\sum_{s_{t+1}} Q(s_{t+1} | s_t )
= \beta \sum_{s_{t+1}} \pi(s_{t+1} | s_t) = \beta.$}
If we substitute \Ep{sintro16} into \Ep{sintro15}, we discover that
$c^i_{t+1}(s_{t+1}) = c^i_t(s_t)$ for all $(s_{t+1}, s_t)$.
Thus, the consumption
of consumer $i$ is constant across time and across states of nature
$s$, so that in equilibrium, all
idiosyncratic risk is insured away.
Higher present-value-of-endowment consumers will have permanently higher
consumption than lower present-value-of-endowment consumers, so that there
is a nondegenerate cross-section distribution of wealth and consumption.
In this model, the cross-section distributions of wealth and consumption
replicate themselves over time, and furthermore each individual forever
occupies the same position in that distribution.
\auth{Quadrini, V.}\auth{R\'\i os-Rull, J.V.} \auth{Perri,Fabrizio}\auth{Krueger, Dirk}%
\auth{Davies, James B.}\auth{Shorrocks, Anthony F.}\auth{Rodriquez, S.B.}%
\auth{Diaz-Gim\' enez, J.}%
A model that has the cross-section distribution of wealth and consumption
being time invariant is not a bad approximation to the data.
But there is ample evidence that individual
households' positions {\it within\/} the distribution of wealth move over
time.\NFootnote{See D\'\i az-Gim\' enez, Quadrini and R\'\i os-Rull (1997);
Krueger and Perri (2004, 2006); Rodriguez, D\'\i az-Gim\' enez, Quadrini
and R\'\i os-Rull (2002); and Davies and Shorrocks (2000).} Several models
described in this book alter consumers' trading opportunities in
ways designed
to frustrate risk sharing enough to cause individuals' position
in the distribution of wealth to change with luck and enterprise.
One class that emphasizes luck is the set of incomplete markets
models started by Truman Bewley. It eliminates the household's
access to almost all markets and returns it to the environment of
the precautionary savings model.
\subsection{Bewley models}
At first glance,
the precautionary savings model with $\beta R=1$ seems like
a bad starting point
for building a theory
that aspires to explain a situation in which cross-section distributions
of consumption and wealth are constant over time even as individuals
experience random fluctuations within that distribution.
A panel of households described by the precautionary savings model with
$\beta R =1$ would have cross-section distributions of wealth
and consumption that march upward and never settle down. What
have come to be called Bewley models are constructed by lowering
the interest rate $R$ to allow those cross-section distributions
to settle down.\NFootnote{It is worth thinking about the sources of the following differences. In the complete markets model sketched in subsection
\use{sec:intro_complete}, an {\it equilibrium\/} risk-free gross interest rate $R$ satisfies
$R \beta=1$ and each consumer completely smooths consumption across both states and time, so that the
distribution of consumption trivially converges. The precautionary savings model of section \use{sec:intro_precautionary}
{\it assumes\/} that $R \beta =1$ and derives the outcome that each consumer's consumption and financial wealth both diverge toward
$+ \infty$. Why can $\beta R =1$ be compatible with non-exploding individual consumption and wealth levels in the complete markets model
of subsection \use{sec:intro_complete}, but not in the precautionary savings model of subsection \use{sec:intro_precautionary}?}
Bewley models are arranged so that the cross
section distributions of consumption, wealth, and income are
constant over time and so that the asymptotic stationary
distributions of consumption, wealth, and income for an individual
consumer across time equal the corresponding cross-section
distributions across people.
A Bewley model can thus
be thought of as starting with a continuum of consumers operating according to the
precautionary savings model with $\beta R=1$ and its diverging
individual asset process. We then lower the interest rate enough
to make assets converge to a distribution whose cross-section
average clears a market for a risk-free asset. Different
versions of Bewley models are distinguished by what the risk-free
asset is. In some versions it is a consumption loan from one
consumer to another; in others it is fiat money; in others it can
be either consumption loans or fiat money; and in yet others it is
claims on physical capital. Chapter \use{incomplete} studies
these alternative interpretations of the risk-free asset.
\topfigure{chap0pic1}
\centerline{\epsfxsize=3.5true in\epsffile{Bewley_chap1.eps}}
\caption{Mean of time series average of household consumption
as function of risk-free gross interest rate $R$.}
\infiglist{chap01}
\endfigure
As a function of a constant gross interest rate $R$,
Figure \Fg{chap0pic1}
plots the time series average of asset holdings for an
individual consumer. At $R=\beta^{-1}$, the time series mean
of the individual's assets diverges, so that $E a(R)$ is infinite.
For $R < \beta^{-1}$, the mean exists. We require that a continuum
of {\it ex ante\/} identical but {\it ex post\/}
different consumers share the same
time series average $E a(R)$ and also that the distribution of
$a$ over time for a given agent equals the distribution of $A_{t+1}$ at a point in time across
agents. If the
asset in question is a pure consumption loan, we require
as an equilibrium condition that $E a(R) =0$, so that
borrowing equals lending. If the asset is fiat money, then
we require that $E a(R) = {M \over p}$, where $M$ is a fixed stock of fiat
money and $p$ is the price level.
Thus, a Bewley model lowers the interest rate $R$
enough to offset the precautionary savings force that with $\beta R=1$ propels
assets upward
in the savings problem.
Precautionary saving remains an important force in Bewley
models: an increase in the volatility of income generally pushes
the $E a(R)$ curve to the right, driving the equilibrium $R$ downward.
\subsection{History dependence in standard consumption models}
Individuals' positions in the wealth distribution
are frozen in the complete markets model, but not
in the Bewley model, reflecting the absence or presence, respectively,
of {\it history dependence\/} in
equilibrium allocation rules for consumption.
The preceding version of the complete markets model
erases history dependence, while the savings problem model and the
Bewley model do not.
History dependence is present in these models in an easy to handle
recursive way because the household's asset level completely
encodes the history of endowment realizations that it has
experienced. We want a way of representing history dependence
more generally in contexts where a stock of assets does not
suffice to summarize history. History dependence can be
troublesome because without a convenient low-dimensional state
variable to encode history, it requires that there be a separate
decision rule for each date that expresses the time $t$ decision
as a function of the history at time $t$, an object with a number
of arguments that grows exponentially with $t$. As analysts, we have a strong
incentive to find a low-dimensional state variable. Fortunately, economists have
made tremendous strides in handling history dependence with
recursive methods that summarize a history with
a single number and that permit compact time-invariant expressions for
decision rules. We shall discuss history dependence later in this
chapter and will encounter many such examples in chapters
\use{stackel} through \use{wldtrade}.
% \use{credible}, \use{socialinsurance}, and
%\use{socialinsurance2}.
\subsection{Growth theory}
Equation \Ep{sintro1} is also a key ingredient of growth theory
(see chapters \use{linappro} and \use{growth}). In the one-sector
growth
model, a representative household solves a version of the savings problem
in which
the single asset is interpreted as a claim on the return from a
physical capital stock $K$ that enters a constant returns to
scale production function $F(K,L)$, where $L$ is labor input.
When returns to capital are tax free, the theory equates the
gross rate of return $R_{t+1}$ to the gross marginal product of
capital net of depreciation, namely, $F_{k,t+1} +(1-\delta)$, where
$F_k(k,t+1)$ is the marginal product of capital
and $\delta$ is a
depreciation rate. Suppose that we add leisure to the utility
function, so that we replace $u(c)$ with the more
general one-period utility function
$U(c,\ell)$, where $\ell$ is the household's leisure.
Then the appropriate version of the consumption Euler
condition \Ep{sintro1} at equality becomes
$$ U_c(t) = \beta U_c(t+1) [F_k(t+1) + (1-\delta) ]. \EQN sintro40 $$
The constant returns to scale property implies that
$F_k(K,N) = f'(k)$, where $k=K/N$ and $F(K,N)=N f(K/N)$.
If there exists a steady state in which $k$ and $c$ are constant over time,
then equation \Ep{sintro40} implies that
it must satisfy
$$ \rho + \delta = f'(k) \EQN sintro41 $$
where $\beta^{-1} \equiv (1+\rho)$. The value of $k$ that solves this equation
is called the ``augmented Golden rule'' steady-state level of the capital-labor
ratio. This celebrated equation shows how technology (in the form of
$f$ and $\delta$) and time preference (in the form of $\beta$) are the
determinants of the steady-state level of capital when income from
capital is not taxed. However, if income from capital is
taxed at the flat rate marginal
rate $\tau_{k,t+1}$,
then the Euler equation \Ep{sintro40} becomes modified
$$ U_c(t) = \beta U_c(t+1) [F_k(t+1) (1-\tau_{k,t+1})
+ (1-\delta) ]. \EQN sintro42 $$
If the flat rate tax on capital is constant and if a steady-state
$k$ exists, it must satisfy
$$ \rho + \delta = (1-\tau_k) f'(k) . \EQN sintro45 $$
This equation shows how taxing capital diminishes the steady-state
capital labor ratio. See chapter \use{linappro} for an extensive
analysis of the one-sector growth model when the government levies
time-varying flat rate taxes on consumption, capital, and labor,
as well as offering an investment tax credit.
\subsection{Limiting results from dynamic optimal taxation}
Equations \Ep{sintro41} and \Ep{sintro45} are central to the
dynamic theory of optimal taxes. Chamley (1986) and Judd (1985b)
\auth{Judd, Kenneth L.}\auth{Chamley, Christophe}%
forced the
government to finance an exogenous stream of government purchases,
gave it the capacity to levy time-varying flat rate taxes on labor
and capital at different rates, formulated an optimal taxation
problem (a so-called Ramsey problem), and studied the possible
limiting behavior of the optimal taxes. Two Euler equations play
a decisive role in determining the limiting tax rate on capital in
a nonstochastic economy: the household's Euler equation
\Ep{sintro42}, and a similar consumption Euler equation for the
Ramsey planner that takes the form
$$ W_c(t) = \beta W_c(t+1) [F_k(t+1) + (1-\delta) ]\EQN sintro43 $$
where
$$ W(c_t, \ell_t) = U(c_t,\ell_t) + \Phi[U_c(t) c_t - U_\ell(t) (1-\ell_t) ]
\EQN sintro44 $$
and where $\Phi$ is a Lagrange multiplier on the government's
intertemporal budget constraint. As Jones, Manuelli, and Rossi
(1997) emphasize,\auth{Jones, Larry E.}\auth{Manuelli, Rodolfo}
\auth{Rossi, Peter E.}%
if the function $W(c,\ell)$ is simply viewed
as a peculiar utility function, then what is called the primal
version of the Ramsey problem can be viewed as an ordinary
optimal growth problem with period utility function $W$ instead of
$U$.\NFootnote{\label{fnt:conflict1}Notice that so long as $\Phi >0$ (which occurs
whenever taxes are necessary), the objective in the primal version
of the Ramsey problem disagrees with the preferences of the
household over $(c,\ell)$ allocations. This conflict is the source
of a time-inconsistency problem in the Ramsey problem with
capital.}
In a Ramsey allocation, taxes must be such that {\it both\/}
\Ep{sintro40} and \Ep{sintro43} always hold, among other equations.
Judd and Chamley note the following implication of the two
Euler equations \Ep{sintro40} and \Ep{sintro43}.
If the government expenditure sequence converges and if
a steady state exists in which $c_t, \ell_t, k_t, \tau_{kt}$ all converge,
then it must be true that \Ep{sintro41} holds {\it in addition\/}
to \Ep{sintro45}.
But both of these conditions can prevail only
if $\tau_k =0$. Thus, the steady-state properties of two versions of our consumption
Euler equation \Ep{sintro1} underlie Chamley and Judd's remarkable result
that asymptotically it is optimal not to tax capital.
In stochastic versions of dynamic optimal taxation problems, we shall glean
additional insights from
\Ep{sintro1} as embedded in the asset-pricing
equations \Ep{sintro7a} and \Ep{sintro8a}.
In optimal taxation problems,
the government has the ability to manipulate asset prices through its
influence on the equilibrium consumption allocation that
contributes to the stochastic discount factor $m_{t+1,t}$ defined in equation \Ep{sintro7a} below.
The Ramsey government seeks a way wisely
to use its power to
revalue its existing debt by altering state-history
prices. To appreciate what the Ramsey government is doing, it helps to know
the theory of asset pricing.
\auth{Lucas, Robert E., Jr.} \auth{Breeden, Douglas T.}
\subsection{Asset pricing}
The dynamic asset pricing theory of Breeden (1979) and Lucas (1978)
also starts with \Ep{sintro1}, but alters what is fixed and what is
free. The Breeden-Lucas
theory is silent about the endowment process $\{y_{t}\}$ and sweeps
it into the background. It
fixes a function $u$ and a discount factor $\beta$,
and takes a consumption process $\{c_t\}$ as given. In particular,
assume that $c_t = g(X_t)$, where $X_t$ is a Markov process with
transition c.d.f.\ $F(X'|X)$. Given these inputs, the theory is assigned the task of
restricting the rate
of return on an asset, defined by Lucas as a
claim on the consumption endowment:
$$ R_{t+1} = {p_{t+1} + c_{t+1} \over p_t}$$
where $p_t$ is the price of the asset. The Euler inequality
\Ep{sintro1} becomes
$$ E_t \beta {u'(c_{t+1}) \over u'(c_t)}\left({p_{t+1} + c_{t+1}
\over p_t}\right) =1. \EQN sintro6 $$
This equation can be solved for a pricing function
$p_t =p(X_t)$. In particular, if we substitute $p(X_t)$ into
\Ep{sintro6}, we get Lucas's functional equation for
$p(X)$.
\subsection{Multiple assets}
If the consumer has access to several assets,
a version of \Ep{sintro1} holds for each
asset:
$$ E_t \beta {u'(c_{t+1}) \over u'(c_t)} R_{j,t+1} =1 \EQN sintro7 $$
where $R_{j,t+1}$ is the gross rate of return on asset $j$.
Given a utility function $u$, a discount factor $\beta$,
and the hypothesis of rational expectations (which allows the researcher
to use empirical projections as counterparts of the theoretical projections
$E_t$),
equations \Ep{sintro7} put extensive restrictions across the moments
of a vector time series for $[c_t, R_{1,t+1}, \ldots, R_{J,t+1}]$.
A key finding of the literature (e.g., Hansen and Singleton, 1983)
is that for $u$'s with plausible
curvature,\NFootnote{Chapter \use{assetpricing2} describes Pratt's (1964)
mental
experiment for deducing plausible curvature.}
consumption is too smooth for $\{c_t, R_{j,t+1}\}$ to satisfy
equation \Ep{sintro7}, where $c_t$ is measured as aggregate
consumption.
Lars Hansen and others have elegantly organized this evidence as follows.
Define the stochastic discount factor $$m_{t+1,t} = \beta {u'(c_{t+1} )
\over u'(c_t)} \EQN sintro7a $$
and write \Ep{sintro7} as
$$ E_t m_{t+1,t} R_{j,t+1} = 1 . \EQN sintro8 $$
Represent the gross rate of return as
$$ R_{j,t+1} = {o_{t+1} \over q_t } $$
where $o_{t+1}$ is a one-period payout on the asset and $q_t$ is
the price of the asset at time $t$. Then \Ep{sintro8} can be expressed
as
$$ q_t = E_t m_{t+1,t} o_{t+1}. \EQN sintro8a $$
The structure of \Ep{sintro8a} justifies calling $m_{t+1,t}$
a stochastic discount factor: to determine the price of an
asset, multiply the random payoff for each state by the discount factor
for that state, then add over states by taking a conditional expectation.
Applying the definition of a conditional covariance and a Cauchy-Schwartz
inequality to this equation implies
$$ {q_t \over E_t m_{t+1,t}} \geq E_t o_{t+1} -
{\sigma_t(m_{t+1,t}) \over E_t m_{t+1,t}} \sigma_t(o_{t+1}) \EQN sintro9 $$
where $\sigma_t(y_{t+1})$ denotes the conditional standard deviation of
$y_{t+1}$.
Setting $o_{t+1}=1$ in \Ep{sintro8a} shows that $E_t m_{t+1,t}$ must be
the time $t$
price of a risk-free one-period security. Inequality
\Ep{sintro9} bounds the ratio of the price of a risky security $q_t$
to the price of a risk-free security $E_t m_{t+1,1}$ by the right side,
which equals the expected
payout on that risky asset {\it minus\/} its conditional
standard deviation $\sigma_t(o_{t+1})$ {\it times\/}
a ``market price of risk''
${\sigma_t(m_{t+1,t}) / E_t
m_{t+1,t}}$.
%An efficient portfolio attains this bound.
By using data only on payouts $o_{t+1}$ and prices $q_t$,
inequality \Ep{sintro9} has been used to estimate the market price
of risk without restricting how $m_{t+1,t}$ relates
to consumption.
If we take these atheoretical estimates of
${\sigma_t(m_{t+1,t}) / E_t
m_{t+1,t}}$
and compare them with the theoretical
values of
${\sigma_t(m_{t+1,t}) / E_t
m_{t+1,t}}$ that we get
with a
plausible curvature for $u$, and
by imposing $\hat m_{t+1,t} = \beta {u'(c_{t+1})\over u'(c_t)}$ for aggregate
consumption,
we find that the theoretical
$\hat m$ has far too little volatility to account for the
atheoretical estimates of the conditional coefficient of variation
of $m_{t+1,t}$. As we discuss extensively in chapter \use{assetpricing2},
this outcome reflects the fact that aggregate consumption is too
smooth to account for atheoretical estimates of the market price of risk.
There have been two broad types of response to the empirical challenge.
The first retains \Ep{sintro8} but abandons \Ep{sintro7a} and instead
adopts
a statistical model for $m_{t+1,t}$. Even without the link that
equation \Ep{sintro7a} provides to consumption, equation
\Ep{sintro8} imposes restrictions across asset returns and
$m_{t+1,t}$ that can be used to identify the $m_{t+1,t}$ process.
Equation \Ep{sintro8} contains no-arbitrage conditions that
restrict the joint behavior of returns. This has been a fruitful
approach in the affine term structure literature (see Backus and
Zin (1993), Piazzesi (2000), and Ang and Piazzesi
(2003)).\NFootnote{Affine term structure models generalize earlier
models that implemented rational expectations versions of the
expectations theory of the term structure of interest rates. See
Campbell and Shiller (1991), Hansen and Sargent (1991), and
Sargent (1979).} \auth{Campbell, John Y.} \auth{Piazzesi, Monika}
\auth{Ang, Andrew} \auth{Hansen, Lars P.} \auth{Zin, Stanley E.}
\auth{Backus, David K.}
Another approach has been to disaggregate and
to write the household-$i$ version of \Ep{sintro1}:
$$ \beta E_t R_{t+1} {u'(c_{i,t+1}) \over u'(c_{it})} \leq 1, \quad
= \ \ {\rm if} \ A_{i,t+1} > \underline A_i. \EQN sintro10 $$ If at
time $t$, a subset of households are on the corner, \Ep{sintro10}
will hold with equality only for another subset of households.
Households in the second set price assets.\NFootnote{David
Runkle (1991) and Gregory Mankiw and Steven Zeldes (1991)
checked \Ep{sintro10}
for subsets of agents.} \auth{Mankiw, Gregory} \auth{Zeldes,
Stephen P.}\auth{Runkle, David}
Chapter \use{socialinsurance2} describes a model of Harald Zhang
(1997) and Alvarez and Jermann (2000, 2001). The model introduces
participation (collateral) constraints and shocks in a way that
makes a changing subset of agents $i$ satisfy \Ep{sintro10}.
Zhang and Alvarez and Jermann formulate
these models by adding participation constraints to the recursive
formulation of the consumption problem based on \Ep{sintro22}.
Next we briefly describe the structure of these models and their
attitude toward our theme equation, the consumption Euler
equation \Ep{sintro1}. The idea of Zhang and Alvarez and Jermann
was to meet the empirical asset pricing challenges by disrupting
\Ep{sintro1}. As we shall see, that requires eliminating some
of the assets that some of the households can trade. These
advanced models exploit a convenient method for representing and
manipulating history dependence. \auth{Zhang, Harold}
\auth{Alvarez, Fernando} \auth{Jermann, Urban}
\section{Recursive methods}
The pervasiveness of the consumption Euler inequality will be a
significant substantive theme of this book. We now turn to a
methodological theme, the imperialism of the recursive method
called dynamic programming.
The notion that underlies dynamic programming
is a finite-dimensional object called the
{\it state\/} that,
from the point of view of current and future payoffs,
completely summarizes the current situation
of a decision maker.
If an optimum problem has a low-dimensional state vector,
immense simplifications follow. A recurring theme of modern macroeconomics
and of this book is that
finding an appropriate state vector is an art.
To illustrate the idea of the state in a simple setting,
return to the savings problem and assume that the
consumer's endowment process is a time-invariant function
of a state $s_t$ that follows a Markov process with time-invariant one-period
transition density $\pi(s'|s)$ and initial density $\pi_0(s)$,
so that $y_t = y(s_t)$.
To begin, recall the description
\Ep{sintro5}
of consumption
that prevails
in the special linear quadratic version of the savings problem. Under our
present assumption that $y_t$ is a time-invariant function of the Markov
state, \Ep{sintro5} and the household's budget constraint imply
the following representation of the household's decision rule:
$$\EQNalign{ c_t & = f(A_t, s_t) \EQN sintro21;a \cr
A_{t+1} & = g( A_t, s_t) . \EQN sintro21;b \cr} $$
Equation \Ep{sintro21;a} represents consumption as a
time-invariant function of a state vector $(A_t, s_t)$. The Markov
component $s_t$ appears in
\Ep{sintro21;a} because it contains all of the information
that is useful in forecasting future endowments (for the linear quadratic
model, \Ep{sintro5} reveals the household's incentive to forecast future
incomes), and the asset level $A_t$ summarizes the individual's current financial
wealth. The $s$ component is assumed to be
exogenous to the household's decisions
and has a stochastic motion governed by $\pi(s'|s)$.
But the future path of $A$ is chosen by the household and is described
by \Ep{sintro21;b}. The system formed by \Ep{sintro21} and the Markov
transition density $\pi(s'|s)$ is said to be {\it recursive\/}
because
it expresses a current decision $c_t$ as a function of the state and tells how
to update the state.
By iterating \Ep{sintro21;b},
notice that $A_{t+1}$ can be expressed as a function of
the history $[s_t, s_{t-1}, \ldots,
s_0]$
and $A_0$. The endogenous state variable financial wealth thus
encodes all payoff-relevant aspects of the history of the
exogenous component of the state $s_t$.
Define the value function $V(A_0,s_0)$ as the optimum value
of the savings problem starting from initial state $(A_0, s_0)$.
The value function $V$ satisfies the following functional
equation, known as a Bellman equation:
$$ V(A,s) = \max_{c,A'}\left\{ u(c) + \beta E[ V(A',s') |s] \right\}
\EQN sintro50 $$
where the maximization is subject to
$A' = R(A+y-c)$ and $y = y(s)$.
Associated with a solution $V(A,s)$ of the Bellman equation is
the pair of policy functions
$$\EQNalign{ c & = f(A,s) \EQN sintro51;a \cr
A' & = g(A,s) \EQN sintro51;b \cr} $$
from \Ep{sintro21}.
The {\it ex ante\/} value (i.e., the value of
\Ep{sintro2} before $s_0$ is drawn)
of the savings problem
is then
$$ v(A_0) = \sum_{s} V(A_0,s) \pi_0(s) . \EQN sintro52 $$
We shall make ample use of the {\it ex ante\/} value function.
\subsection{Dynamic programming and the Lucas Critique}
Dynamic programming is now recognized as
a powerful method for studying private
agents' decisions and also the decisions
of a government that wants to design an optimal
policy in the face of constraints imposed on it by private agents'
best responses to that government policy. But it has taken
a long time for the power of dynamic programming to be realized
for government policy design problems.
Dynamic programming had been applied since the late 1950s
to design government decision rules
to control an economy whose transition laws included
rules that described the decisions of private agents.
In 1976 Robert E. Lucas, Jr.,\ published his now famous critique of
dynamic-programming-based econometric
policy evaluation procedures.
The heart of Lucas's critique was
the implication for government policy evaluation of
a basic property that pertains to any optimal decision rule
for private agents with a form
\Ep{sintro51} that attains a Bellman equation like \Ep{sintro50}.
The property is that the optimal decision rules $(f,g)$ depend on
the transition density $\pi(s'|s)$ for the exogenous component of
the state $s$. As a consequence, any widely understood government
policy that alters the law of motion for a state variable like
$s$ that appears in private agents' decision rules should alter
those private decision rules. (In the applications that Lucas
had in mind, the $s$ in private agents' decision problems included
variables useful for predicting tax rates, the money supply, and
the aggregate price level.) Therefore, Lucas asserted that
econometric policy
evaluation procedures that assumed that private agents' decision
rules are fixed in the face of alterations in government policy
are flawed.\NFootnote{They were flawed because they assumed ``no
response'' when they should have assumed ``best response'' of private
agents' decision rules to government decision rules.}
Most econometric policy evaluation procedures at the time
were vulnerable to Lucas's criticism.
To construct valid policy evaluation procedures,
Lucas advocated building new models that
would attribute rational expectations to decision makers.\NFootnote{That
is, he wanted private decision rules to solve dynamic programming
problems with the correct transition density $\pi$ for $s$.}
Lucas's discussant Robert Gordon predicted that after that ambitious
task had been accomplished, we could then use dynamic programming
to compute optimal policies, i.e., to solve Ramsey problems.
\subsection{Dynamic programming challenged}
But Edward C.
Prescott's 1977 paper
entitled ``Should Control Theory Be Used for Economic Stabilization?''
asserted that Gordon was too optimistic.
Prescott
claimed that in his 1977 JPE paper with
Kydland he had proved that
it was ``logically impossible'' to use dynamic programming to find
optimal government policies in settings where private traders
face genuinely dynamic problems. Prescott
said that dynamic programming was inapplicable to government policy
design problems because the structure of
best responses of {\it current private decisions\/} to {\it future\/}
government policies prevents the government policy design problem from
being recursive (a
manifestation of the time inconsistency of optimal government plans).
The optimal government plan would therefore require a government
commitment technology, and the government policy
must take the form of a sequence of history-dependent
decision rules that could not be expressed as a function
of natural state variables.
\subsection{Imperialistic response of dynamic programming}
Much of the subsequent history of macroeconomics
belies
Prescott's claim of ``logical impossibility.''
More and more problems that smart
people like Prescott in 1977 thought could not be attacked
with dynamic programming {\it can\/} now be solved with
dynamic programming.
Prescott didn't put it this way in 1977, but today we would:
in 1977 we lacked a way to handle history dependence
within a dynamic programming framework.
Finding a recursive way to
handle history dependence is a major achievement of the past 35 years
and an important methodological theme of this book that opens
the way to a variety of important applications.
We shall encounter important traces of
the fascinating history of this topic in various chapters. Important
contributors to the task of overcoming Prescott's challenge seemed to work in isolation
from one another, being unaware of the complementary approaches
being followed elsewhere. Important contributors included
Shavell and Weiss (1979);
Kydland and Prescott (1980); Miller and Salmon (1985); Pearlman;
Currie and Levine (1985); Pearlman (1992), and Hansen, Epple, and
Roberds (1985). These researchers achieved truly independent
discoveries of the same important idea. \auth{Salmon, Mark}
\auth{Miller, Marcus} \auth{Pearlman, J. G.}\auth{Levine, P.L.}
\auth{Currie, D.A.}\auth{Weiss, Laurence}\auth{Shavell, Stephen}
\auth{Kydland, Finn E.}\auth{Prescott, Edward C.}\auth{Hansen,
Lars P.} \auth{Roberds, William}
As we discuss in detail in chapter \use{stackel},
one important approach amounted to putting a government costate vector
on the costate equations of the private decision makers,
then proceeding as usual to use optimal control for the government's
problem.
(A costate equation
is a version of an Euler equation.)
Solved forward, the costate equation
depicts the dependence of private decisions on forecasts
of future government policies that Prescott was worried about.
The key idea in this approach was to formulate
the government's problem by taking the costate
equations of the private sector as additional {\it constraints\/}
on the government's problem. These amount to promise-keeping
constraints (they are cast in terms of derivatives of value functions,
not value functions themselves, because costate vectors are
gradients of value functions). After adding the costate equations
of the private sector (the ``followers'') to the transition
law of the government (the ``leader''), one could then solve
the government's problem by using dynamic programming as usual.
One simply writes down a Bellman equation for the government
planner taking the private sector costate variables as
pseudo-state variables. Then it is almost business as
usual (Gordon was correct!). We say ``almost'' because after the
Bellman equation is solved, there is one more step: to pick the
initial value of the private sector's costate. To maximize the government's
criterion, this initial
condition should be set to zero because initially there are no
promises to keep. The government's optimal decision is a
function of the natural state variable {\it and\/} the costate
variables.
The date $t$
costate variables encode history and record the ``cost'' to the
government at $t$ of confirming the private sector's prior expectations
about the government's time $t$ decisions, expectations
that were embedded in the private sector's decisions before $t$.
The solution is time inconsistent (the government would always like to
reinitialize the time $t$ multiplier to zero and thereby discard
past promises, but that is ruled out by the assumption that the
government is committed to follow the optimal plan).
See chapter \use{stackel} for many technical details, computer programs,
and an application.
\subsection{History dependence and ``dynamic programming squared''}
Rather than pursue the ``costate on the costate'' approach further,
we now turn to a closely related approach that we illustrate in a
dynamic contract design problem. While superficially
different from the government policy design problem, the contract problem
has
many features in common with it. What is again needed is a recursive way
to encode history dependence. Rather than use costate variables,
we move up a derivative and work with promised values. This leads
to value functions appearing inside value functions or
``dynamic programming squared.''
Define the history $s^t$ of the Markov state
by $s^t = [s_t, s_{t-1}, \ldots, s_0]$ and let $\pi_t(s^t)$ be the
density over histories induced by $\pi, \pi_0$.
Define a consumption allocation rule
as a sequence of functions, the time component of which maps
$s^t$ into a choice of time $t$ consumption, $c_t = \sigma_t(s^t)$, for
$t \geq 0$.
Let $c= \{\sigma_t(s^t)\}_{t=0}^\infty$.
Define the ({\it ex ante\/}) value associated with an allocation
rule as
$$v(c) = \sum_{t=0}^\infty \sum_{s^t} \beta^t u(\sigma_t(s^t)) \pi_t(s^t).
\EQN sintro60 $$
For each possible realization of the period zero state $\overline s_0$,
there is a {\it continuation history\/} $s^t|_{\overline s_0}$.
The observation that a continuation history is itself a complete history
is our first hint that a recursive formulation is
possible.\NFootnote{See chapters \use{recurge} and \use {credible}
for discussions of the recursive structure of histories.}
For each possible realization of the first period $s_0$,
a consumption allocation rule implies a one-period {\it continuation
consumption rule\/} $c|_{\overline s_0}$. A continuation consumption
rule is itself a consumption rule that maps histories into
time series of consumption.
The one-period continuation history
treats the time $t+1$ component of the original history evaluated
at $\overline s_0$ as the time $t$
component of the continuation history.
The period $t$ consumption of the
one-period continuation consumption allocation conforms to the
time $t+1$ component of original consumption allocation evaluated
at $\overline s_0$.
The time and state separability of \Ep{sintro60} then allow us to
represent $v(c)$ recursively
as
$$ v(c) = \sum_{s_0} [ u(c_0(s_0) )+ \beta v(c|_{s_0})]\pi_0(s_0) ,
\EQN sintro61 $$
where $v(c|_{s_0})$ is the value of the continuation allocation.
We call $v(c|_{s_0})$ the continuation value.
In a special case
that successive components of $s_t$ are i.i.d.\ and have a discrete
distribution,
we can write \Ep{sintro61} as
$$ v = \sum_s [u(c_s) + \beta w_s ] \Pi_s, \EQN sintro22 $$
where $\Pi_s = {\rm Prob}(y_t = \overline y_s)$ and
$[\overline y_1 < \overline y_2 \cdots < \overline y_S]$
is a grid on which the endowment resides,
$c_s$ is
consumption in state $s$ given $v$, and $w_s$ is the continuation
value in state $s$ given $v$.
Here we use $v$ in \Ep{sintro22} to denote what was $v(c)$ in \Ep{sintro61}
and $w_s$ to denote what was $v(c|_s)$ in \Ep{sintro61}.
%The qualification `given $v$' is very important because in this
%notation $v$ encodes all
%history dependence.
So far this has all been for an arbitrary consumption plan.
Evidently, the {\it ex ante\/}
value $v$ attained by an {\it optimal\/} consumption program must
satisfy
$$ v = \max_{\{{c_s, w_s}\}_{s=1}^S} \sum_s [u(c_s) + \beta w_s ] \Pi_s
\EQN sintro23 $$ where the maximization is subject to constraints
that summarize the individual's opportunities to trade current
state-contingent consumption $c_s$ against future state-contingent
continuation values $w_s$. In these problems, the value of $v$ is
an outcome that depends, in the savings problem for example, on
the household's initial level of assets. In fact, for the savings
problem with i.i.d.\ endowment shocks, the outcome is that $v$ is
a monotone function of $A$. This monotonicity allows the following
remarkable representation. After solving for the optimal plan, use
the monotone transformation to let $v$ replace $A$ as a state
variable and represent the optimal decision rule in the form
$$\EQNalign{ c_s & = f(v,s) \EQN sintro24;a \cr
w_s & = g(v,s) . \EQN sintro24;b \cr} $$
%which are of the form \Ep{sintro21} with the state $s$ indexing the endowment
%$y$, the initial promised $v$ taking the role of $A$, and
%$w_s$ being the continuation value, i.e., next period's value of $A$.
The promised value $v$ (a forward-looking variable if there ever was one)
is also the variable that
functions as an index of history in \Ep{sintro24}. Equation
\Ep{sintro24;b} reminds us that $v$ is a ``backward looking'' variable
that registers the cumulative impact of past states $s_t$.
The definition of $v$ as a promised value, for example in
\Ep{sintro23}, tells us that $v$ is also a forward-looking variable
that encodes expectations (promises) about future consumption.
\subsection{Dynamic principal-agent problems}
The right side of \Ep{sintro23} tells the terms on which
the household is willing
to trade
current utility for continuation utility.
Models that confront enforcement and information problems use the
trade-off identified by \Ep{sintro23} to design intertemporal
consumption plans that optimally balance risk sharing and intertemporal
consumption smoothing against the need to offer correct incentives.
Next we turn to such models.
We remove the household from the market and hand it over to a
planner or principal who offers the household a contract that the
planner designs to deliver an {\it ex ante\/} promised value $v$