title | jupyter | ||||||||||||||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
FoS Coq notebook |
|
Adapted from a workshop given at POPL 2008.
The point of this workshop is to give you a feel for what is it like to do proofs in Coq, and also to illustrate what the Curry-Howard isomorphism really is and what are its applications. This workshop is not graded, and you will not see Coq during the exam (though there's a big chance you'll see Curry-Howard, and you may see a fragment of CoC).
However, we cannot actually properly teach you how to do proofs in Coq or to explain everything we will do in details, because we simply don't have enough time for that. In case you are interested in knowing more, you can go through this notebook (or its full version, check the README here) in detail yourself, you could read the Software Foundations book, and you could take a look at the Certified Programming with Dependent Types book.
During the lecture, you have already seen how we can formulate CoC on paper. In this notebook, we will be working with Coq, an interactive theorem assistant with a type system based on an extension of CoC. The differences are slight, but they are there, so let's start by inspecting them.
First things first: you can use the Check
command to inspect types of terms.
Check 0.
Naturally, we type 0
as nat
.
Check nat.
If we think in terms of set theory, then all nat
s form a Set
.
More to the point, Set
in Coq is a kind of types that represent data
(more on this in a second).
We can define our own types with the Inductive
command:
Inductive nat' : Set :=
| zero'
| succ' (n : nat')
.
The Inductive
command introduces an inductive data type, inductive in this
case meaning being defined inductively. The above definition is basically the
same as the following Scala definition:
sealed trait Nat
final case object Zero extends Nat
final case class Succ(n: Nat) extends Nat
We say that zero'
and succ'
are constructors for the nat'
type, since they
are the fundamental/primitive way of constructing values of type nat'
. They are
themselves values or functions:
Check zero'.
Check succ'.
And they can also be used to destruct/pattern match on values of type nat'
:
Fixpoint add (n : nat') (m : nat') : nat' :=
match n with
| zero' => m
| succ' n => add n (succ' m)
end.
Coq is an interactive theorem assistant, so we'd like to use it to do some
proofs. Recall that by the Curry-Howard isomorphism, types are propositions and
terms that inhabit them are proofs that those propositions are true.
Then, if we want to do proofs about whether a number is even or not,
we first thing need to define a type for this proposition. Specifically, if n
is even, we would like to be able to construct a value of type is_even' n
(note that is_even'
will need to be a type operator). We can define
is_even'
as follows:
Inductive is_even' : nat' -> Prop :=
| zero_even' : is_even' zero'
| double_succ_even' (n : nat') (p : is_even' n) : is_even' (succ' (succ' n))
.
As expected, we needed to annotate is_even'
with nat' -> Prop
as its type,
meaning it's a type operator from nat'
s to a propositions (more on Prop
in a
second). We have two constructors for this proposition, and both of them now
have annotations for their result types.
The first one, zero_even'
, is a proof that 0 is even, and accordingly its type
is is_even' zero'
. The other one is more complicated. We can understand it as
follows: if we want to prove that n+2
is even, we need to have n
(naturally)
and we need a proof that n
is even -- a value of type is_even' n
.
We can also type function literals with dependent function types.
For instance, say that we want to take a value of type is_even' n
and we want to apply double_succ_even'
to this value twice --
in this case, we want to take a value n
and use it in a type,
so we need a term-dependent function type. Here's a definition of this
function in Coq:
Check fun n : nat' =>
fun p : is_even' n =>
double_succ_even' _ (double_succ_even' _ p).
(Ignore the underscores for now, they are for boring arguments.)
The type of this value has the form forall n : nat', t
.
That's the Coq equivalent of (n : nat') -> t
(or Π(n : nat')t
)
from CoC.
Believe it or not, the above value is a proof of a trivial statement --
namely, that if n
is even, then so is n + 4
.
You can read out loud this value's type as follows: "for all n, n being even
implies that n+4 is even".
Why the underscores? Because double_succ_even'
actually needs two arguments,
an n : nat'
and a p : is_even' n
. The value for the first one can be figured
out based on the type of the second one, so with an underscore we can tell Coq
exactly that -- to figure out for us what value should be passed there. Neat.
Now, let's come back to Set
. You may have noticed that for is_even'
, we've
used Prop
instead. What are those things? Well, here's what Coq can tell us:
Check Set.
Check Prop.
Both Set
and Prop
are universes of "proper" types, in the sense of the *
sort you've seen in CoC, whereas Type
is the equivalent of the "box" sort. How
come we have two variants of *
? The short answer is: Set
is the universe of
data, while Prop
is the universe of propositions. That's honestly as much
as you need to understand in order to work with Coq.
The longer answer is that there's multiple small differences between them, all
aligned with the above intuition. Values from Set
can be "extracted" to create
OCaml programs, while values from Prop
cannot (and will in fact be ignored
when extracting values from Set
). Set
is predicative (meaning universal
types can't quantify over other universal types, like in Hindley-Milner), while
Prop
is impredicative (meaning universal types are as powerful as in System
F). On the basis of the proof irrelevance principle, we assume that any two values
of the same type from Prop
are equal. We do not do the same for types in Set
,
which allows us the nice property that 0
is different from 1
and, more generally,
allows distinguishing any two values via, for instance, pattern matching.
There's other differences as well, but again: you don't actually need to know
any of them 99% of the time.
Recall the types of zero'
and succ'
:
Check zero'.
Check succ'.
We could also define nat'
by annotating each constructor with its type, as follows:
Inductive nat' : Set :=
| zero' : nat'
| succ' : nat' -> nat'
.
This is more convenient for more complex definitions, so we will be using this form from now on.
Now, let's start the actual workshop!
During your first project, you worked with the NB language, a trivial system that had natural numbers, booleans and some basic operations for them. In this notebook, we will be working with a very similar language. We will use Coq to encode terms from the NB language, as well as basic judgments and some simple proofs.
The grammar of our language would be defined as follows:
t ::= "true" terms
| "false"
| "if" t "then" t "else" t
| 0
| "succ" t
| "pred" t
| "iszero" t
We will represent these terms in Coq with tm
, an inductive data type:
Inductive tm : Set :=
| tm_true : tm
| tm_false : tm
| tm_if : tm -> tm -> tm -> tm
| tm_zero : tm
| tm_succ : tm -> tm
| tm_pred : tm -> tm
| tm_iszero : tm -> tm.
This definition is mostly straightforward -- for every rule in the grammar, there's a corresponding constructor. Using the above definition, we can create values corresponding to the terms in our language:
(* Represents the term "if (iszero 0) then false else true" *)
Check (tm_if (tm_iszero tm_zero) tm_false tm_true).
Next, we want to define what it means to be a value in our language. While in
the original NB language we did so through grammar rules, it's equally valid to
define judgments which tells us which terms are boolean and numeric values.
The judgments will have the form ⊢ bvalue t
and ⊢ nvalue t
(for reasons
which will become clear in a second). They are defined as follows:
⊢ bvalue true (b_true)
⊢ bvalue false (b_false)
⊢ nvalue 0 (n_zero)
⊢ nvalue t
----------------- (n_succ)
⊢ nvalue (succ t)
How do we represent these judgments in Coq? Both bvalue
and nvalue
will need
to be type operators, like is_even'
. A judgment is clearly a proposition, so
they will both be Prop
s. The actual definitions are as follows:
Inductive bvalue : tm -> Prop :=
| b_true : bvalue tm_true
| b_false : bvalue tm_false.
Inductive nvalue : tm -> Prop :=
| n_zero : nvalue tm_zero
| n_succ : forall t,
nvalue t ->
nvalue (tm_succ t).
We have one constructor per each axiom and inference rule -- observe that the
constructor types are actually quite similar to the rules they represent.
We had to assign n_succ
a dependent function type, since the corresponding
inference rule is implicitly quantified with a t
.
Let's emphasize again what we have. The type nvalue t
represents the
proposition that t
is a numeric value. For instance, nvalue (tm_succ tm_zero)
represents the proposition that the successor of zero (or simply one)
is a numeric value. To show that this proposition is true, we need to construct
a value of said type. We can do that as follows:
(** Note: n_succ needs two arguments, a `t : tm` and an `nvalue t`. *)
Check (n_succ tm_zero n_zero).
As the last thing in this section, we will (finally) define what it means to be
a value. In Coq, T \/ S
is the data type corresponding to the proof that
either T
or S
is true. If we use it, the definition is simple enough:
Definition value (t : tm) : Prop :=
bvalue t \/ nvalue t.
Having defined tm
s and value
s, we can define call-by-value operational
semantics for our language.
Formally, reduction was a relation between terms.
In Coq, we will define an inductive data type eval (t : tm) (t' : tm) : Prop
corresponding to the proposition that t
evaluates to t'
in a single step.
The definition is as follows:
Inductive eval : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| e_iftrue : forall t2 t3,
eval (tm_if tm_true t2 t3) t2
| e_iffalse : forall t2 t3,
eval (tm_if tm_false t2 t3) t3
| e_if : forall t1 t1' t2 t3,
eval t1 t1' ->
eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) (tm_if t1' t2 t3)
| e_succ : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval (tm_succ t) (tm_succ t')
| e_predzero :
eval (tm_pred tm_zero) tm_zero
| e_predsucc : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval (tm_pred (tm_succ t)) t
| e_pred : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval (tm_pred t) (tm_pred t')
| e_iszerozero :
eval (tm_iszero tm_zero) tm_true
| e_iszerosucc : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval (tm_iszero (tm_succ t)) tm_false
| e_iszero : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval (tm_iszero t) (tm_iszero t').
If you don't feel comfortable with Coq syntax yet, compare the above with the definition of beta-reduction from our first assignment.
Next, we define the multi-step evaluation relation eval_many
, corresponding to multi-step beta-reduction.
Its inference rules are:
------------- (m_refl)
eval_many t t
eval t t' eval_many t' u
--------------------------- (m_step)
eval_many t u
And its definition is:
Inductive eval_many : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| m_refl : forall t,
eval_many t t
| m_step : forall t t' u,
eval t t' ->
eval_many t' u ->
eval_many t u.
Note The exercises below may be hard. If you find yourself stuck when doing them, copy the definitions from solutions here - they will be useful later on.
Exercise Multi-step evaluation is often defined as the "reflexive,
transitive closure" of single-step evaluation. Write an inductively defined
relation eval_rtc
that corresponds to that verbal description.
In case you get stuck or need a hint, you can find solutions to all the exercises near the bottom of the file.
(** Write your solution here *)
Exercise Sometimes it is more convenient to use a big-step semantics for a
language. Add the remaining constructors to finish the inductive definition
full_eval
for the big-step semantics that corresponds to the small-step
semantics defined by eval
. Build the inference rules so that full_eval t v
logically implies both eval_many t v
and value v
. In order to do this, you
may need to add the premise nvalue v
to the appropriate cases.
Hint: You should end up with a total of 8 cases.
(**
Inductive full_eval : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| f_value : forall v,
value v ->
full_eval v v
| f_iftrue : forall t1 t2 t3 v,
full_eval t1 tm_true ->
full_eval t2 v ->
full_eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) v
| f_succ : forall t v,
nvalue v ->
full_eval t v ->
full_eval (tm_succ t) (tm_succ v).
*)
So far, we've only seen proofs represented in Coq as manually-constructed values. For any non-trivial proof value, it's rather inconvenient to manually construct it.
Proof values are most easily built interactively, using tactics to manipulate a proof state. A proof state consists of a set of goals (propositions or types for which you must produce an inhabitant), each with a context of hypotheses (inhabitants of propositions or types you are allowed to use). A proof state begins initially with one goal (the statement of the lemma you are trying to prove) and no hypotheses. A goal can be solved, and thereby eliminated, when it exactly matches one of hypotheses in the context. A proof is completed when all goals are solved.
Tactics can be used for forward reasoning (which, roughly speaking, means modifying the hypotheses of a context while leaving the goal unchanged) or backward reasoning (replacing the current goal with one or more new goals in simpler contexts). Given the level of detail required in a formal proof, it would be ridiculously impractical to complete a proof using forward reasoning alone. However it is usually both possible and practical to complete a proof using backward reasoning alone. Therefore, we focus almost exclusively on backward reasoning in this tutorial. Of course, most people naturally use a significant amount of forward reasoning in their thinking process, so it may take you a while to become accustomed to getting by without it.
We use the keyword Lemma
to state a new proposition we wish to prove.
(Theorem
and Fact
are exact synonyms for Lemma
.) The keyword Proof
,
immediately following the statement of the proposition, indicates the beginning
of a proof script. A proof script is a sequence of tactic expressions, each
concluding with a .
. Once all of the goals are solved, we use the keyword
Qed
to record the completed proof. If the proof is incomplete, we may tell Coq
to accept the lemma on faith by using Admitted
instead of Qed
.
We now proceed to introduce the specific proof tactics.
- [intros]
- [apply]
- [apply with (x := ...)]
Recall that both implication and universal quantification correspond to function
types and values. Accordingly, we can use the intros
tactic to move
universally quantified variables and implication antecedents from the goal into
the context as hypotheses.
If our current goal corresponds to a conclusion of some implication P
, we can
use the apply P
tactic to prove our goal by proving the antecedents of P
. If
you'd suspect from the name of the tactic that this corresponds to applying a
function, you'd be correct. Using apply
allows building a proof value from the
bottom up.
In the following example, we will create a value corresponding to a (still) simple proposition. Step through every cell below to see how this value is constructed.
Lemma e_succ_pred_succ : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t).
Proof.
(** Let [t] be a [tm]. *)
intros t.
(** Assume that [t] is an [nvalue] (and let's call that
assumption [Hn] for future reference). *)
intros Hn.
(** By [e_succ], in order to prove our conclusion, it suffices
to prove that [eval (tm_pred (tm_succ t)) t]. *)
Check e_succ.
apply e_succ.
(** That, in turn, can be shown by [e_predsucc], if we are
able to show that [nvalue t]. *)
Check e_predsucc.
apply e_predsucc.
(** But, in fact, we assumed [nvalue t]. *)
apply Hn.
Qed.
At this point, we have successfully concluded our proof; e_succ_pred_succ
is a
value that can be used like any other value we have seen so far. It corresponds
to the following proof tree:
nvalue t
---------------------------- (e_predsucc)
eval (tm_pred (tm_succ t)) t
------------------------------------------------ (e_succ)
eval (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t)
We can see the value we have constructed with the following command:
Print e_succ_pred_succ.
Compare the value to the proof script above. Observe how function application in
the value corresponds to usages of apply
tactic.
Now consider, for a moment, the rule m_step
:
eval t t' eval_many t' u
------------------------- (m_step)
eval_many t u
If we have a goal such as eval_many e1 e2
, we should be able to use apply m_step
in order to replace it with the goals eval e1 t'
and eval_many t' e2
. But what exactly is t'
here? When and how is it chosen? It stands to
reason the conclusion is justified if we can come up with any t'
for which the
premises can be justified.
Now we note that, in the Coq syntax for the type of m_step
, all three
variables t
, t'
, and u
are universally quantified. The tactic apply m_step
will use pattern matching between our goal and the conclusion of
m_step
to find the only possible instantiation of t
and u
. However, apply m_step
will raise an error since it does not know how it should instantiate
t'
. In this case, the apply
tactic takes a with
clause that allows us to
provide this instantiation. This is demonstrated in the proof below.
Observe how this works in the proof script below. The proof tree here gives a visual representation of the proof term we are going to construct and the proof script has again been annotated with the steps in English.
Letting s = tm_succ
p = tm_pred
lem = e_succ_pred_succ,
nvalue t
- - - - - - - - - - - - (lem) --------------------- (m_refl)
eval (s (p (s t))) (s t) eval_many (s t) (s t)
------------------------------------------------------ (m_step)
eval_many (s (p (s t))) (s t)
Lemma m_succ_pred_succ : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval_many (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t).
Proof.
(** Let [t] be a [tm], and assume [nvalue t]. *)
intros t Hn.
(** By [m_step], to show our conclusion, it suffices to find
some [t'] for which
[eval (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) t']
and
[eval t' (tm_succ t)].
Let us choose [t'] to be [tm_succ t]. *)
Check m_step.
apply m_step with (t' := tm_succ t).
(** By the lemma [e_succ_pred_succ], to show
[eval (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t)],
it suffices to show [nvalue t]. *)
Check e_succ_pred_succ.
apply e_succ_pred_succ.
(** And, in fact, we assumed [nvalue t]. *)
apply Hn.
(** Moreover, by the rule [m_refl], we also may conclude
[eval (tm_succ t) (tm_succ t)]. *)
Check m_refl.
apply m_refl.
Qed.
Write proof scripts for the following lemmas, following the plain language descriptions.
These lemmas will be useful in later proofs.
Lemma m_one : forall t1 t2,
eval t1 t2 ->
eval_many t1 t2.
(** Let [t1] and [t2] be terms, and assume [eval t1 t2]. We
may conclude [eval_many t1 t2] by [m_step] if we can find
a term [t'] such that [eval t1 t'] and [eval_many t' t2].
We will choose [t'] to be [t2]. Now we can show
[eval t1 t2] by our assumption, and we can show
[eval_many t2 t2] by [m_refl]. *)
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
Lemma m_two : forall t1 t2 t3,
eval t1 t2 ->
eval t2 t3 ->
eval_many t1 t3.
(** Let [t1], [t2], and [t3] be terms. Assume [eval t1 t2]
and [eval t2 t3]. By [m_step], we may conclude that
[eval_many t1 t3] if we can find a term [t'] such that
[eval t1 t'] and [eval_many t' t3]. Let's choose [t'] to
be [t2]. We know [eval t1 t2] holds by assumption. In
the other case, by the lemma [m_one], to show [eval_many
t2 t3], it suffices to show [eval t2 t3], which is one of
our assumptions. *)
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
Lemma m_iftrue_step : forall t t1 t2 u,
eval t tm_true ->
eval_many t1 u ->
eval_many (tm_if t t1 t2) u.
(** Let [t], [t1], [t2], and [u] be terms. Assume that
[eval t tm_true] and [eval_many t1 u]. To show
[eval_many (tm_if t t1 t2) u], by [m_step], it suffices to
find a [t'] for which [eval (tm_if t t1 t2) t'] and
[eval_many t' u]. Let us choose [t'] to be
[tm_if tm_true t1 t2]. Now we can use [e_if] to show that
[eval (tm_if t t1 t2) (tm_if tm_true t1 t2)] if we can
show [eval t tm_true], which is actually one of our
assumptions. Moreover, using [m_step] once more, we can
show [eval_many (tm_if tm_true t1 t2) u] where [t'] is
chosen to be [t1]. Doing so leaves us to show
[eval (tm_if tm_true t1 t2) t1] and [eval_many t1 u]. The
former holds by [e_iftrue] and the latter holds by
assumption. *)
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
- [split]
- [left]
- [right]
- [destruct] (for conjunction and disjunction)
Example If H
is the name of a conjunctive hypothesis, then destruct H as p
will
replace the hypothesis H
with its components using the names in the pattern
p
. Observe the pattern in the example below.
Lemma m_two_conj : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' /\ eval t' t'' ->
eval_many t t''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' H.
destruct H as [ He1 He2 ].
apply m_two with (t2 := t').
apply He1.
apply He2.
Qed.
Example Patterns may be nested to break apart nested structures. Note that
infix conjunction is right-associative, which is significant when trying to
write nested patterns. We will later see how to use destruct
on many different
sorts of hypotheses.
Lemma m_three_conj : forall t t' t'' t''',
eval t t' /\ eval t' t'' /\ eval t'' t''' ->
eval_many t t'''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' t''' H.
destruct H as [ He1 [ He2 He3 ] ].
apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply He1.
apply m_two with (t2 := t'').
apply He2.
apply He3.
Qed.
Example If your goal is a conjunction, use split
to break it apart into
two separate subgoals.
Lemma m_three : forall t t' t'' t''',
eval t t' ->
eval t' t'' ->
eval t'' t''' ->
eval_many t t'''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' t''' He1 He2 He3.
apply m_three_conj with (t' := t') (t'' := t'').
split.
apply He1.
split.
apply He2.
apply He3.
Qed.
Exercise Hint: You might find lemma m_three
useful here.
Lemma m_if_iszero_conj : forall v t2 t2' t3 t3',
nvalue v /\ eval t2 t2' /\ eval t3 t3' ->
eval_many (tm_if (tm_iszero tm_zero) t2 t3) t2' /\
eval_many (tm_if (tm_iszero (tm_succ v)) t2 t3) t3'.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
Example If we have a disjunction in the context, we can use destruct
to
reason by cases on the hypothesis. Note the syntax of the associated pattern.
Lemma e_if_true_or_false : forall t1 t2,
eval t1 tm_true \/ eval t1 tm_false ->
eval_many (tm_if t1 t2 t2) t2.
Proof.
intros t1 t2 H. destruct H as [ He1 | He2 ].
apply m_two with (t2 := tm_if tm_true t2 t2).
apply e_if. apply He1.
apply e_iftrue.
apply m_two with (t2 := tm_if tm_false t2 t2).
apply e_if. apply He2.
apply e_iffalse.
Qed.
- [destruct] (for inductively defined propositions)
- [induction]
Example Use destruct
to reason by cases on an inductively defined datatype
or proposition.
Lemma e_iszero_nvalue : forall v,
nvalue v ->
eval (tm_iszero v) tm_true \/
eval (tm_iszero v) tm_false.
Proof.
intros v Hn.
destruct Hn.
(* Case [n_zero].
Note how [v] becomes [tm_zero] in the goal. *)
left.
apply e_iszerozero.
(* Case [n_succ].
Note how [v] becomes [tm_succ v] in the goal. *)
right.
apply e_iszerosucc. apply Hn.
Qed.
Example You can use induction
to reason by induction on an inductively
defined datatype or proposition. This is the same as destruct
, except that it
also introduces an induction hypothesis in the inductive cases.
Lemma m_iszero : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many (tm_iszero t) (tm_iszero u).
Proof.
intros t u Hm. induction Hm.
apply m_refl.
apply m_step with (t' := tm_iszero t').
apply e_iszero. apply H.
apply IHHm.
Qed.
Work on the following exercise.
Exercise
Lemma m_trans : forall t t' u,
eval_many t t' ->
eval_many t' u ->
eval_many t u.
(** We proceed by induction on the derivation of
[eval_many t t'].
Case [m_refl]: Since [t] and [t'] must be the same, our
conclusion holds by assumption.
Case [m_step]: Now let's rename the [t'] from the lemma
statement to [u0] (as Coq likely will) and observe that
there must be some [t'] (from above the line of the
[m_step] rule) such that [eval t t'] and
[eval_many t' u0]. Our conclusion follows from from
an application of [m_step] with our new [t'] and our
induction hypothesis, which allows us to piece together
[eval_many t' u0] and [eval_many u0 u] to get
[eval_many t' u]. *)
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
Exercise Prove the following lemma.
Hint: You may be interested in some previously proved lemmas, such as m_one
and m_trans
.
Note: Even though this lemma is in a comment, its solution is also at the
bottom. (Coq will give an error if we leave it uncommented since it mentions the
eval_rtc
relation, which was the solution to another exercise.)
(**
Lemma eval_rtc_many : forall t u,
eval_rtc t u ->
eval_many t u.
*)
Exercise Prove the following lemma.
(**
Lemma eval_many_rtc : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_rtc t u.
*)
Exercise Prove the following lemma.
(**
Lemma full_eval_to_value : forall t v,
full_eval t v ->
value v.
*)
Inductive eval_rtc : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| r_eval : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval_rtc t t'
| r_refl : forall t,
eval_rtc t t
| r_trans : forall t u v,
eval_rtc t u ->
eval_rtc u v ->
eval_rtc t v.
Inductive full_eval : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| f_value : forall v,
value v ->
full_eval v v
| f_iftrue : forall t1 t2 t3 v,
full_eval t1 tm_true ->
full_eval t2 v ->
full_eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) v
| f_iffalse : forall t1 t2 t3 v,
full_eval t1 tm_false ->
full_eval t3 v ->
full_eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) v
| f_succ : forall t v,
nvalue v ->
full_eval t v ->
full_eval (tm_succ t) (tm_succ v)
| f_predzero : forall t,
full_eval t tm_zero ->
full_eval (tm_pred t) tm_zero
| f_predsucc : forall t v,
nvalue v ->
full_eval t (tm_succ v) ->
full_eval (tm_pred t) v
| f_iszerozero : forall t,
full_eval t tm_zero ->
full_eval (tm_iszero t) tm_true
| f_iszerosucc : forall t v,
nvalue v ->
full_eval t (tm_succ v) ->
full_eval (tm_iszero t) tm_false.
Lemma m_one_sol : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval_many t t'.
Proof.
intros t t' He. apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply He.
apply m_refl.
Qed.
Lemma m_two_sol : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' ->
eval t' t'' ->
eval_many t t''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' He1 He2. apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply He1.
apply m_one. apply He2.
Qed.
Lemma m_iftrue_step_sol : forall t t1 t2 u,
eval t tm_true ->
eval_many t1 u ->
eval_many (tm_if t t1 t2) u.
Proof.
intros t t1 t2 u He Hm.
apply m_step with (t' := tm_if tm_true t1 t2).
apply e_if. apply He.
apply m_step with (t' := t1).
apply e_iftrue.
apply Hm.
Qed.
Lemma m_if_iszero_conj_sol : forall v t2 t2' t3 t3',
nvalue v /\ eval t2 t2' /\ eval t3 t3' ->
eval_many (tm_if (tm_iszero tm_zero) t2 t3) t2' /\
eval_many (tm_if (tm_iszero (tm_succ v)) t2 t3) t3'.
Proof.
intros v t2 t2' t3 t3' H.
destruct H as [ Hn [ He1 He2 ] ]. split.
apply m_three with
(t' := tm_if tm_true t2 t3) (t'' := t2).
apply e_if. apply e_iszerozero.
apply e_iftrue.
apply He1.
apply m_three with
(t' := tm_if tm_false t2 t3) (t'' := t3).
apply e_if. apply e_iszerosucc. apply Hn.
apply e_iffalse.
apply He2.
Qed.
Lemma two_values_sol : forall t u,
value t /\ value u ->
bvalue t \/
bvalue u \/
(nvalue t /\ nvalue u).
Proof.
unfold value. intros t u H.
destruct H as [ [ Hb1 | Hn1 ] H2 ].
left. apply Hb1.
destruct H2 as [ Hb2 | Hn2 ].
right. left. apply Hb2.
right. right. split.
apply Hn1.
apply Hn2.
Qed.
Lemma m_trans_sol : forall t u v,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many u v ->
eval_many t v.
Proof.
intros t u v Hm1 Hm2. induction Hm1.
apply Hm2.
apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply H.
apply IHHm1. apply Hm2.
Qed.
Lemma eval_rtc_many_sol : forall t u,
eval_rtc t u ->
eval_many t u.
Proof.
intros t u Hr. induction Hr.
apply m_one. apply H.
apply m_refl.
apply m_trans with (t' := u).
apply IHHr1.
apply IHHr2.
Qed.
Lemma eval_many_rtc_sol : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_rtc t u.
Proof.
intros t u Hm. induction Hm.
apply r_refl.
apply r_trans with (u := t').
apply r_eval. apply H.
apply IHHm.
Qed.
Lemma full_eval_to_value_sol : forall t v,
full_eval t v ->
value v.
Proof.
intros t v Hf. induction Hf.
apply H.
apply IHHf2.
apply IHHf2.
right. apply n_succ. apply H.
right. apply n_zero.
right. apply H.
left. apply b_true.
left. apply b_false.
Qed.